1/33
Looks like no tags are added yet.
Name | Mastery | Learn | Test | Matching | Spaced |
---|
No study sessions yet.
Interesting questions in public choice
Why do some individuals in a community seem to follow conventions?
Why do we drive on the right side of the road?
How are large number of people able to coordinate their behavior?
Why do we participate in protests or armed groups?
How do we make sure that people do their fair share of collective undertaking?
How do we make sure that each person in our household does part of the cleaning?
Do groups uniformly represent the interest of their members?
Mancur Olson
1932 - 1998
Former professor of Economics at the University of Maryland
A prominent figure in Political Economy and Public Choice
Public financing and public policy
Political economy
International Relations e.g., economic theory of alliances
Olson: the logic of collective action
Collective action problems became a large topic within RC after Mancur Olson's publication of "The Logic of Collective Action" in 1965
Prior to this, scholars took groups for granted, assuming they were a natural state of social and political affairs
Furthermore, many believed that groups representing the wide array of interests in a society would 'naturally' form to represent these interests
Olson's work demonstrated that these assumptions were false
Olson: the logic of collection action main arguments
rational and self-interested individuals will not act voluntarily to achieve their common or group interests
Collective action is problematic if we talk about public goods
Public goods
non-excludable (available to everyone)
Non-rival (the goods do not disappear→ ex lighthouse)
What public goods actually meet these criteria?
clean air
National defence
Lighthouses
Highways
Private goods
excludable and rival
Raise no collective action problems
Olson and public goods
Olson (1965:12) defines public good solely on the basis of excludability
However, public goods are also defined in terms of their non-rivalrous
This suggest that his theory also applies to common pool
resources
Common pool resources
Goods that are non-excludable but rivalrous
Ex. Environment, fishing grounds
Public goods: non-excludability
It means that if some members of a group achieve a public good, then every member of the group gets to enjoy this good, whether or not the member contributed to the achievement of the good
However, in most cases excludability is a matter of cost
Example:The owners of a Lighthouse could arrange for a series of ships carrying giant black-out screens to sail directly in front of any boat which had not paid to use the lighthouse beam...
What does non-excludability incentivize?
Free-riding
Collective action problem
"Any group or any organization, large or small, works for some collective benefit that by its nature will benefit all of the members of that group in question. Though all members of a group therefore have a common interest in paying costs of providing that collective good. Each would prefer that the others ay the entire cost, and ordinarily would get any benefit provided whether he has borne part of the cost or not"
RCT and collective action problem
The assumptions of RC lead to pessimistic conclusions about the willingness of individuals to engage in collective action
And... when RCT correctly predicts that individuals will not rationally pursue a common interest, this is often a
"problem" in that a common good is not obtained
Example: voting paradox
In a large election, the probability that an individual vote might change the election outcomes is extremely small
If each person only votes for the purpose of influencing the election outcome, then even a small cost to vote - like bad weather - should dissuade anyone from voting
Bc I don’t determine the election outcome, the cost of voting should be too high
Going there
Biking
Etc.
Example: voting paradox economist view
Economist ask why the voter turnout is so high bc they deem it irrational
The only reason you should go vote is bc you think that your vote will have an effect on outcome
In reality your one vote makes no difference on end result
The cost of voting is higher than the expected benefit of it = voting is irrational
Example: voting paradox theory vs reality
Instrumental voting model: an action has value only if it affects outcomes
However, we observe that many people do vote...
This inconsistency between the theory and real-world turnout rates is known as the "paradox of (not) voting"
How can we explain this? Why do people vote anyway?
Social pressure
Internal/individual pressure
Example: voting paradox theories
Expressive theories: the act of voting itself gives utility, which can depend on various factors (how other people vote,…
Bounded rationality voter theories: weaken the full rationality assumptions of voters
Example: security dilemma
Realist argue that in an anarchical system, states confront a 'security dilemma'
The more one state arms itself, the more reason other states have to either accelerate their own rearmament of contemplate a pre-emptive attack
Yet, even if it is in the interest of every country that everyone disarms, it may not be in the interest of any one country to be the first to do so
Key factor in collective action problem occurring according to Olson?
Group size
"Indeed, unless the number of individuals in a group is quite small, or unless there is coercion or some other special device to make individuals act in their common interest, rational, self-interested individuals will not act to achieve their common or group interests."
Group size: small groups
According to Olson, the free-riding problem is common to all groups
But collective action problems are easier to overcome when the size of the group is small
The effectiveness of each individual is rather large in a small group
Each individual contribution makes a noticeable difference → free-riding is much harder in smaller groups bc you will be able to detect them
Because each member matters, the other members have incentives to make sure everyone is cooperating
Small groups still have problems, specifically the exploitation of the "large" by the "small"
The larger the group the harder it is to find free-riders
Group size: large groups
Collective action problems are most severe in large groups
Individual contributions may matter less
Free-riders are difficult to identify → anonymous in large groups
Free-riders difficult to punish
Thus, large groups often remain "latent" (plagued by free-riders)
The types of groups likely to remain latent are those that represent broad societal interests
What really matters is the difference an individual contribution makes to the pursuit of the public good
Examples of solutions to the collective action problem
state provides public goods
How well is the gov capable of supplying public goods? The gov changes, which could change how much public goods they provide
Can have long term problems/costs
Large members/political entrepreneurs have a stronger incentive to engage in cooperative behavior and produce a public good
Privatization
Pay to have access to
Ex. Fishing rights, pollution vouchers
By-products and selective incentives
Examples of solutions: by-products and selective incentives
This is Olson's explanation for the existence of large-scale collective action
Groups can entice members to join by providing selective incentives - i.e., benefits (private goods) that can be obtained only by contributing
Selective incentives are private and exclusive; they are "rewards" for being a member of the group
Selective incentives can be positive (i.e., a reward) or negative (i.e., a fine, bad for reputation)
Selective incentives example
Negative selective incentives
Punishment or costs to only those who fail to contribute to the provision of collective good
State coercion and regulation: if you do not pay tax, you will go to jail
Govs can solve many collective action problems
Non-state actors such as warlords or the Mafia can also enforce rules and regulations
Enforcement problems
costly enforcement
Enforcement is not costless; small departures form cooperative agreements are likely to go unpunished
Imperfect enforcement
Think about judges making the wrong call and send the wrong person to prison
Enforcer incentives
We assume that enforcers are honest, but…
Ex. Racial profiling
Elinor Ostrom
Female political scientist who won the Nobel Prize in economics (!!!) in 2009
She won the prize for her "analysis of economic governance, especially the commons"
Ostrom, Elinor (1990). Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
Field research
Governing the commons basics
Detailed case studies of the management of common pool resources
Goods that are non-excludable but rivalrous Ex. Fishing grounds
She shows that over-time groups of individuals have developed complex formal and informal rules of allocation to overcome collective action problems
She argued strongly against Garrett Hardin (1968) and his idea of the "Tragedy of the Commons"
Garret Hardin
1968), biologist
Racist (!) and anti-immigrant
Against welfare state; which promotes the tragedy
Restatement of Olson's argument with respect to latent groups and common pool resources
Tragedy of the commons: the problem
Every individual has an incentive to consume a resource, but at the expense of every other individual
There is no way to exclude anyone from consuming
Negative results
As the demand for the resource overwhelms the supply, every individual who consumes an additional unit directly harms others—and themselves too-who can no longer enjoy the benefits
Commons: a piece of land for everyone to use for livestock etc
Used in old towns
Tragedy of the commons: Hardin’s solution
either privatization or state control
Governing the commons
Ostrom rejected the idea of the outside solution
Instead, she argued that individuals can escape collective action problems by converging on informal norms or crafting formal rules to facilitate cooperation
Privatization or nationalization will often be unnecessary
Additionally, Ostrom shows that it might even be counterproductive
Governing the commons NOTE
Norms will not always arise to solve collective action problems!
It will only be adopted by individuals if it is somehow in their own interest
Governing the commons: example
Privatization of a lake
Might solve overfishing but might also prevent non-rivalrous use of the lake for transport
Olson vs Ostrom
Ostrom provides many case studies of specific instances of collective action
Ostrom argues against Olson's idea that voluntary cooperation is out of the question in large groups
Ostrom argues against Olson's idea that social incentives do not play any role