1/47
Flashcards on Justice, Ethical Egoism, Utilitarianism for exam review.
Name | Mastery | Learn | Test | Matching | Spaced |
---|
No study sessions yet.
Distributive Justice
How society's resources and opportunities should be fairly shared among individuals and groups.
Original Position
A hypothetical situation where individuals choose the principles of justice without knowing their place in society, behind a veil of ignorance.
Rational Person in Original Position
A rational person would want to maximize the amount of primary social goods that each member of society gets.
Equality of Maximal Rights
Each person must have an equal right to the greatest amount of liberties compatible with a similar liberty for everyone else.
Compensation for Inequalities
Social and economic inequalities are only permissible when they benefit everyone.
Rights supported by Original Position
The right to vote, freedom of speech, freedom of conscience, freedom of thought, freedom of person, the right to hold personal property, freedom from arbitrary arrest, search, and seizure.
Compensation for Inequalities
Prioritizes fairness and individual rights over maximizing total welfare.
Difference Principle
Inequalities are justifiable only if they ultimately improve the situation of the worst-off members of society.
Priority of Equality of Maximal Rights
Even if an inequality benefits everyone, if it restricts the rights or liberties of some group, then it would be impermissible.
Justice for Special Groups
Some special groups deserve special privileges in the rules for society.
Agreement View
A wage is just if and only if it is fairly negotiated by the earner and the business owner(s).
Desert View
A wage is just if and only if it is no higher or lower than what the earner deserves to be paid for the job he or she does.
Utility View
High wages attract and retain talented managers and motivate workers to succeed and compete for them.
Moriarty's first assumption about Desert View
A person’s economic contribution is the only variable that determines what pay a worker deserves.
Moriarty's second assumption about Desert View
there is a mathematical function that determines, given a person’s economic contribution x, how much that person deserves as compensation f (x), and the slope of that function is no greater than y = x (so, f (y) − f (x) ≤ y − x)
Attraction & Retention Utility View
This view says that a level of compensation is morally just if and only if anything lower would fail to attract and retain sufficiently capable workers to the position.
Motivation Utility View
A level of CEO compensation is morally just if and only if anything lower would fail to engender such things as: 1. The motivation of the CEO themselves to work hard, 2. The alignment of the CEO’s motivation with shareholder interests, 3. The motivation of other workers to compete for the CEO position by working hard.
Non-monetary perks objection
Those other jobs have “non-monetary” perks (e.g., the feeling of fulfillment one gets from public service). Top CEO jobs are just as demanding, but lack such perks; therefore, top CEO compensation has to be higher to make up for this and attract sufficiently capable people.
Exceptional People Objection
Sufficiently capable people could be attracted to top CEO jobs if the average salary was lowered substantially, but truly exceptional people wouldn’t be attracted to them.
Friedman's Shareholder Theory
A manager’s primary duty when acting as a manager is to seek to fulfill the business goals of the owners (shareholders).
Unelected Taxation Argument
A manager who in their role as manager pursues “social” goals that are not shareholder goals is acting as a civil servant.
Frederick’s Argument Against Shareholder Theory
If the shareholder account is true, then any business practice that is lawful and that maximizes profit is not immoral.
Stakeholder Theory
Managers have a fiduciary duty not just to shareholders, but to all stakeholders in the company.
Freeman's Legal Argument
Over the last century, the law in many countries (including the US) has evolved to constrain, in many ways, the legal freedom with which managers can pursue profits for shareholders.
Freedom to Dispense Owned Goods principle (FDOG)
No one has a right to an equal chance at a good they do not “own”, hence no one’s rights are violated if the owner distributes it preferentially.
Equal Opportunity for Partly-Owned Goods (EPOG) principle
When an applicant for receiving a good is themselves a part-owner of that good, they have a right to an equal chance at getting it.
Debts of gratitude
If the owners of a good owe a debt of gratitude to someone, then so long as the majority of them agree to do so, they can preferentially dispense that good to that person, and justly override the right to an equal chance at that good that other part-owners of that good may have.
Compensation for the past wrongs
The owners of a good mistreated or harmed someone substantially in the past, then they can preferentially dispense the food they own to that person, an thereby justly override the right to an equal chance at that good that other part-owners of that good my have
Arguments (in the logical sense)
Uses declarative sentences that make a statement that is meant to either be true or false.
Conclusion indicator
A word or phrase that marks a sentence or independent clause as being of an argument’s conclusion.
Premise indicator
Words or phrases used to indicate the premise (reason).
Golden Rule of Logic
An argument is valid and you deny its conclusion then you must also deny at least one of it premises.
Moral Code
A list of rules for behavior.
Moral Universalism
There are some moral rules that APPLY TO everyone no matter what, and these rules SHOULD NEVER be broken by anyone, regardless of if they accept it.
Cultural Relativism
It is morally permissible to do whatever the moral code accepted by your society or culture says is permissible and no rules have to be accepted by all societies or cultures.
Cultural Variation
A descriptive claim that different societies have different moral codes
Moral Skepticism
Moral skeptics claim you don’t know — and cannot ever know — whether those actions are right or wrong.
Individual Relativism
Morality is determined by each individual's beliefs.
Observation Argument Against Moral Universalism
People disagree about morality even after debate. If disagreement persists, then all moral beliefs must be equally correct. If all beliefs are correct, there is no True Moral Code.
Undeniable Wrongs Argument
Some actions (e.g., torturing babies for fun) are always wrong, even if a society accepts them.
Moral Progress Argument
If Cultural Relativism is true, societies can change but cannot morally improve.
One Person Many Cultures Argument
People belong to multiple cultures, which often have conflicting moral codes. No single culture determines morality.
Consequentialism
An action is wrong if and only if there is something else you could do instead that would as a matter of fact have better consequences.
Ethical Egoism
An action is wrong if and only if there is something else you could do that would result in a higher lifetime well-being level for you.
LWL
A person's lifetime well-being level.
Prisoner's Dilemma
The group outcome is not optimal when everyone looks out for their well being
Utilitarianism
An action is wrong (immoral) if and only if there is something else you could do that would result in a higher UHWL.
Universe History Well-being Level (UHWL)
A hypothetical measure of overall well-being across all individuals.