moral philosophy mixed

0.0(0)
learnLearn
examPractice Test
spaced repetitionSpaced Repetition
heart puzzleMatch
flashcardsFlashcards
Card Sorting

1/108

encourage image

There's no tags or description

Looks like no tags are added yet.

Study Analytics
Name
Mastery
Learn
Test
Matching
Spaced

No study sessions yet.

109 Terms

1
New cards

anti-realism, moral

The theory that claims that there are no moral properties. Error theory and moral non-cognitivism are both anti-realist.

2
New cards

applied ethics

The branch of ethics concerned with the application of normative ethical theories to particular issues, such as lying or stealing.

3
New cards

arête

An 'excellence', or more specifically, a 'virtue' - a quality that aids the fulfilment of a thing's ergon (Aristotle).

4
New cards

attitude

A mental state regarding how the world is or should be. A cognitive attitude, e.g. belief, has a mind-to-world direction of fit. A non-cognitive attitude, e.g. desire, has a world-to-mind direction of fit.

5
New cards

belief

Affirmation of, or conviction regarding, the truth of a proposition. E.g. 'I believe that the grass is green.'

6
New cards

Categorical Imperative

Act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.' (Kant)

7
New cards

character

A person's habitual dispositions regarding what they feel, how they think, how they react, the choices they make, and the actions they perform, under different circumstances.

8
New cards

character trait

An attribute that is exhibited by an individual as a matter of habit, e.g. honesty or being bad-tempered.

9
New cards

choice

What we decide upon as a result of deliberation, typically giving rise to voluntary action. Deliberate desire regarding something that is in one's power (Aristotle).

10
New cards

cognitivism

A cognitivist account of ethical language argues that moral judgements express beliefs, can be true or false and aim to describe the world. So 'lying is wrong' expresses the belief that lying is wrong, and is either true or false.

11
New cards

conscience

An inner awareness, faculty, intuition or judgement that assists in distinguishing right from wrong.

12
New cards

consequentialism, act

The theory that actions are morally right or wrong depending on their consequences and nothing else. An act is right if it maximises what is good.

13
New cards

contradiction in conception

In Kantian ethics, the test for whether we can will a maxim to become universal law can be failed if it would somehow be self-contradictory for everyone to act on that maxim.

14
New cards

contradiction in will

In Kantian ethics, the test for whether we can will a maxim to become universal law can be failed if, although the maxim is not self-contradictory, we cannot rationally will it.

15
New cards

deontology

The study of what one must do (deon (Greek) means 'one must'). Deontology claims that actions are right or wrong in themselves, not depending on their consequences. We have moral duties to do things which it is right to do and moral duties not to do things which it is wrong to do.

16
New cards

desirable

1) Worthy of being desired. 2) Capable of being desired.

17
New cards

desire

A state of mind that motivates a person to act in such a way as to satisfy the desire, e.g. if a person desires a cup of tea, they are motivated to make and drink a cup of tea

18
New cards

direction of fit

The direction of the relation between mind and world. In one direction, the mind 'fits' the world, as in belief. We change our beliefs to fit the facts. In the other direction, the world 'fits' the mind, as in desire. We act on our desires to change the world to satisfy our desires.

19
New cards

doctrine of the mean

Aristotle's claim that virtue requires us to feel, choose and act in an 'intermediate' way, neither 'too much' nor 'too little', but 'to feel [passions] at the right times, with reference to the right objects, towards the right people, with the right motive, and in the right way'.

20
New cards

duties, general/specific

Duties are obligations we have towards someone or something. General duties are those we have towards anyone, e.g. do not murder, help people in need. Specific duties are those we have because of our particular personal or social relationships, e.g. to keep one's promises or to provide for one's children.

21
New cards

duties, perfect/imperfect

Perfect duties are those we must always fulfil and have no choice over when or how (e.g. do not kill). Imperfect duties are cases in which we have some choice in how we fulfil the obligation (e.g. giving to charity). No specific person can demand that we fulfil an imperfect duty towards them.

22
New cards

emotivism

The theory that claims that moral judgements express a feeling or non-cognitive attitude, typically approval or disapproval, and aim to influence the feelings and actions of others.

23
New cards

end

What an action seeks to achieve or secure, its aim or purpose.

24
New cards

end, final

An end that we desire for its own sake, we can't give some further purpose for why we seek it.

25
New cards

ergon

'Function' or 'characteristic activity' of something, e.g. the ergon of a knife is to cut, the ergon of an eye is to see.

26
New cards

error theory

The theory that moral judgements make claims about objective moral properties, but that no such properties exist. Thus moral judgements are cognitive, but are all false. Moral language, as we mean to use it, rests on a mistake.

27
New cards

ethics

The branch of philosophy concerned with the evaluation of human conduct, including theories about which actions are right or wrong (normative ethics) and the meaning of moral language (metaethics).

28
New cards

eudaimonia

Often translated as 'happiness', but better understood as 'living well and faring well'. According to Aristotle, eudaimonia is not subjective and is not a psychological state, but an objective quality of someone's life as a whole. It is the final end for human beings.

29
New cards

experience machine

Nozick's thought experiment concerning a virtual reality machine which someone plugs into for life. The machine will create the experience of a very happy life, but Nozick argues that we value being in touch with reality more, so we won't choose to plug in.

30
New cards

faculty

A mental capacity or ability, such as sight, the ability to feel fear, and reason.

31
New cards

felicific calculus

In Bentham's ethics, the means of calculating pleasures and pains caused by an action and adding them up on a single scale. The total amount of happiness produced is the sum total of everyone's pleasures minus the sum total of everyone's pains.

32
New cards

first principles

Basic or foundational propositions in an area of knowledge or theory that are not deducible from other propositions.

33
New cards

formula of humanity

A version of the Categorical Imperative: 'Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means, but always at the same time as an end' (Kant).

34
New cards

function argument

Aristotle's argument that the human good (eudaimonia) will be achieved by performing our characteristic activity (ergon) well. Traits that enable us to fulfil our ergon, which is rational activity, are virtues (arête).

35
New cards

Golden Rule

The moral guideline that says 'do unto others as you would have them do unto you'.

36
New cards

good

In ethics, what is good provides a standard of evaluation and what we should aim at in our actions and lives.

37
New cards

hedonic calculus

see felicific calculus

38
New cards

hedonism

The claim that pleasure is happiness and the only good.

39
New cards

Hume's 'fork'

We can have knowledge of just two sorts of claim: the relations between ideas and matters of fact.

40
New cards

imperative

A command or order. A hypothetical imperative is a statement about what you ought to do, on the assumption of some desire or goal, e.g. if you want to pass your exam, you ought to study hard. A categorical imperative is a statement about what you ought to do, without regard to what you want.

41
New cards

integrity

Acting on and living by the values that you endorse.

42
New cards

intention

A mental state that expresses a person's choice. It specifies the action they choose and often their reason or end in acting.

43
New cards

intuitionism

The theory that some moral judgements are self-evident, i.e. their truth can be known just by rational reflection upon the judgement itself. Moral intuitions are a type of synthetic a priori knowledge.

44
New cards

involuntary

According to Aristotle, an act is involuntary if it is either forced or done from ignorance that is not culpable (especially if it is regretted once the ignorance is removed).

45
New cards

is-ought gap

Hume's claim that judgments about what ought to be the case are very different from judgments about what is the case, and cannot be deduced from them. The claim is made as an objection to moral cognitivism.

46
New cards

justice

The principle that each person receives their 'due'. Aristotle distinguishes between wide and narrow senses. In the wide sense, anything legal is just, and anything illegal is unjust. In the narrow sense, justice is fairness.

47
New cards

justice in distribution

Justice concerning who gets which goods and other resources.

48
New cards

justice in rectification

Justice concerning how to correct an injustice.

49
New cards

maxim

A personal principle that guides our decisions, e.g. 'to get a good education'.

50
New cards

meaning, descriptive

The aspect of the meaning of a sentence that asserts something about the world and can be evaluated as true or false.

51
New cards

meaning, emotive

The aspect of the meaning of a sentence that expresses or evokes an emotion.

52
New cards

meaning, prescriptive

The aspect of the meaning of a sentence that acts like a command or imperative. For example, the prescriptive meaning of 'lying is wrong' might be 'do not lie'.

53
New cards

means

What is done to achieve an end. Instrumental means are actions done to achieve some further, independent end, e.g. chopping vegetables in order to eat them. Constitutive means are those which are done as achieving the end, e.g. relaxing on the beach is a way of having a good holiday.

54
New cards

metaethics

The philosophical study of what morality is, enquiring into the meaning of moral language, the metaphysics of moral values, the epistemology of moral judgements, and the nature of moral attitudes.

55
New cards

mind-dependent

Depending on a mind for existence or definition, e.g. ideas are mind-dependent.

56
New cards

mind-independent

Not depending on a mind for existence or definition. According to realism in perception, physical objects are mind-independent; according to moral realism, moral properties are mind-independent (in some important way).

57
New cards

morality

The rules, ideals and expectations governing fundamental aspects of human conduct. It concerns right and wrong, good and bad, in human action and character.

58
New cards

motive

A mental state or consideration that inclines someone to act in a certain way. Someone's motive could be a reason for acting, an end, or a desire.

59
New cards

naturalism, moral

A form of moral realism that claims that moral properties are natural properties. According to reductive naturalism, moral properties are identical with certain properties that can be identified through sense experience and science, e.g. the claim that goodness is happiness understood as pleasure (a psychological property). According to non-reductive naturalism, moral properties are natural - related to human nature - but not a kind of property that science can investigate, e.g. the good life is eudaimonia (a complex psychological, rational and normative property).

60
New cards

naturalistic fallacy

According to Moore, the mistake of identifying moral good with any natural property.

61
New cards

nihilism

The view that there are no moral values.

62
New cards

non-cognitivism

The theory that claims that moral judgements express non-cognitive attitudes. Moral judgements do not make claims about reality and are not true or false (they are not fact-stating).

63
New cards

non-naturalism, moral

A form of moral realism that claims that moral properties are not natural properties.

64
New cards

non-voluntary

According to Aristotle, an action is non-voluntary if it is done from ignorance and if the ignorance is lifted, the agent does not regret the action.

65
New cards

normative ethics

The branch of ethics concerned with developing theories concerning what (e.g. which actions, which character traits, which intentions) is right or wrong, good or bad.

66
New cards

open question argument

Moore's argument that identifying the property 'good' with any other property is never correct because whether that property is, in fact, good is an open question (logically, it can receive a yes or no answer), whereas whether good is good is not an open question.

67
New cards

partiality

Favouring some people, e.g. family and friends, over others

68
New cards

passions

In Aristotle, bodily appetites (for food, drink, sex, etc.), emotions, desires, and any feelings accompanied by pleasure or pain.

69
New cards

permissible

An action that is neither morally forbidden nor required (obligatory).

70
New cards

pleasures, higher and lower

According to Mill, one pleasure is higher than another if almost everyone who is 'competently acquainted' with both prefers one over the other. Higher pleasures include thought, feeling and imagination, while lower pleasures involve the body and senses.

71
New cards

practical ethics

see applied ethics.

72
New cards

practical reason

Reasons and reasoning concerned with what we can change and making good choices.

73
New cards

practical wisdom

(phronesis) An intellectual virtue of practical reason, 'a true and reasoned state or capacity to act with regard to the things that are good or bad for man' (Aristotle). It involves knowledge of what is good or bad in general and what is good in a particular situation, and the abilities to deliberate well and act on that deliberation.

74
New cards

prescriptivism

The non-cognitive theory that moral judgements are prescriptive, that is, moral judgements provide commands and recommendations about how to act.

75
New cards

property, moral

An attribute or characteristic of an object that is ethically normative, e.g. goodness or being a virtue.

76
New cards

property, natural/non-natural

Natural properties are those that we can identify through sense experience and science. Non-natural properties cannot be analysed in terms of or reduced to natural properties.

77
New cards

queerness, argument from

Mackie's argument that moral properties, understood as non-natural properties, are (metaphysically and epistemologically) puzzling and improbable, which is a reason to believe they do not exist.

78
New cards

realism, moral

The theory that claims that moral judgements are made true or false by objective moral properties that exist and are mind-independent (in some sense).

79
New cards

relativism

The theory that some area of discourse, e.g. concerning truth, knowledge or morality, is 'relative to' a society or person. According to relativism, a proposition may be true 'for' one person but not another; or an action may be morally right in one society but not another.

80
New cards

responsibility, moral

Accountability for the actions one performs and the consequences they bring about, for which a moral agent can be justly praised or blamed. Moral responsibility is commonly held to require the agent's freedom to have done otherwise.

81
New cards

right reason

(orthos logos) In Aristotle, the standard for judging whether a character trait or an action conforms to the mean. Virtues and right actions are in accordance with 'right reason'.

82
New cards

rights

Justified moral demands regarding how other people may treat us, especially the freedoms (e.g. from harm) or benefits (e.g. education) they ought to provide. We are entitled to our rights in the sense that others have a moral obligation to respect them.

83
New cards

secondary principles

In Mill, moral 'rules of thumb' that, if followed, generally produce happiness, e.g. 'tell the truth'. Mill argues that we have learned secondary principles through human history, through trial and error.

84
New cards

sentience

The ability to feel, perceive, or experience subjectively, in particular the capacity to experience pleasure and pain.

85
New cards

simulated killing

The dramatisation of killing within a fictional context, e.g. in video games, films and plays. It is not merely the description of a killing, as in a novel, but a fictional enactment of killing that the audience or gamer can see and hear.

86
New cards

skill analogy

The analogy between virtues and practical skills. In Aristotle, virtues are said to be like practical skills because we learn both through practice (what we do), not (just) theory; and we gain an expertise that is sensitive to individual situations.

87
New cards

soul

In Aristotle, that part of the person that relates to mind and life. According to Aristotle, the soul has three parts - a part relating to being alive, a part characterised by desires and emotions that are responsive to reason, and rational intellect.

88
New cards

speciesism

Unfair discrimination on the basis of what species something belongs to.

89
New cards

stealing

Taking someone else's property with no intention of returning it and without their permission (or without the legal right to do so).

90
New cards

subjectivism

The theory that moral judgements assert or report approval or disapproval, e.g. 'Murder is wrong' means 'Most people disapprove of murder'.

91
New cards

subjectivism, speaker

The theory that moral judgements assert the approval or disapproval of the speaker, e.g. 'Murder is wrong' means 'I disapprove of X'. Therefore, whether a moral judgement is true or false depends on the attitudes of the speaker.

92
New cards

theoretical reason

Reasons and reasoning concerned with what we can't change and what is true.

93
New cards

tyranny of the majority

The unjust exercise of power by a majority of people over a minority who have different values or desires, e.g. outlawing a minority religion because most people want it outlawed.

94
New cards

universalise

To apply to everything/everyone.

95
New cards

utilitarianism

The theory that only happiness is good, and the right act (or rule) is that act (or rule) that maximises happiness.

96
New cards

utilitarianism, act

The theory that only happiness is good, and the right act is that act that maximises happiness. Hedonist act utilitarianism understands happiness in terms of the balance of pleasure over pain.

97
New cards

utilitarianism, preference

The theory that we should maximise happiness, which is understood not in terms of pleasure and pain, but in terms of the satisfaction of people's preferences.

98
New cards

utilitarianism, rule

The theory that only happiness is good, and the right act is that act that complies with those rules which, if everybody followed them, would lead to the greatest happiness (compared to any other set of rules).

99
New cards

utility

The property of an object or action in virtue of which it tends to produce happiness.

100
New cards

utility, principle of

The defining principle of act utilitarianism: 'that principle which approves or disapproves of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose interest is in question' (Bentham).