Claire Herbert discusses the implications of moral error theory, particularly in the context of the ‘Now What’ Problem—what should error theorists do with moral judgments that they now deem false?
The paper examines two proposed solutions: moral fictionalism and moral abolitionism.
Moral Error Theory: All moral judgments are false; objective moral values do not exist (Mackie, 1977).
Moral Fictionalism: Morality is treated as a useful fiction; society continues to act as if moral values exist despite knowing they do not.
Moral Abolitionism: The recommendation to eliminate moral language and judgments if objective moral values are believed to not exist.
After denying objective morality, error theorists face the question of whether to still act as if it exists or to discard moral discourse entirely.
The Now What Problem: Questions what moral error theorists should do with their moral beliefs post-conviction that they are false.
Mackie's claim: There are no objective values (1977); all our past moral assertions are false.
Error theorists assert that while society behaves as if objective morality exists, in reality, they are mistaken.
The paper posits that the discussion centers on what error theorists should do with the moral judgments deemed incorrect.
Motivations Behind Fictionalism:
Argues that pretending morality exists can prevent temptation and create societal benefits, as seen through benefit-cost analyses of morality.
Fictionalists maintain that despite understanding morality as fiction, they still derive benefits from adhering to it as if it were true.
Critique of Fictionalism:
For morality to guide actions, belief in its existence is necessary; without belief, the motivation is lost.
Counterexamples show that one cannot be motivated by something they outright deny exists (e.g., belief in Father Christmas).
Moral commands only effectively instruct behavior if the individual believes in them.
Joyce's assertion that fictional rules motivate as leverage may overlook the deeper psychological mechanics of motivation.
The paper promotes a mild form of moral abolitionism, suggesting that eliminating moral language and judgment wouldn’t lead to drastic societal consequences.
Abolitionists hold that if morality does not exist, conceptualizing and discussing it should cease, paralleling the rationalization behind discarding non-existent concepts like Phlogiston.
Common Objections:
A prevalent fear is that the absence of morality will lead to selfishness and societal collapse. The paper refutes this by emphasizing that humans possess various non-selfish motivations for behavior.
Individuals can still act altruistically based on self-interest, empathy, and a desire for social cooperation, irrespective of moral obligations.
Personal Ethics:
Personal ethical frameworks can exist outside of objective morality. Abolitionists can establish personal codes or ethical habits that help govern behavior.
The investigation articulates that while fictionalism posits benefits to preserving moral discussions, these benefits are contingent upon belief.
Herbert argues for moral abolitionism as a more grounded solution, asserting it doesn’t inherently diminish societal function or ethical behavior. Instead, it opens the scope for a society operating on non-moral reasons and empathy without being constrained by objective moral values.