CE

Scientific Anti-Realism: Constructive Empiricism

Scientific Realism vs. Scientific Anti-Realism

  • Scientific realism: the view that the best explanation of the success of science is that our mature theories are (approximately) true and their central, theoretical terms refer to real, mind-independent entities.
  • Scientific anti-realism: umbrella term for positions that reject truth (or approximate truth) as science’s primary aim and/or deny that we can justifiably believe in unobservable entities.
  • The transcript focuses on one prominent anti-realist form: Constructive Empiricism (CE).

Constructive Empiricism (Bas van Fraassen, 1980-present)

  • Name breakdown:
    • “Constructive”: emphasizes the active, intentional construction of models that scientists build.
    • “Empiricism”: emphasizes that knowledge claims should not outrun the observable evidence.
  • Semantic agreement with realists:
    • Both CE and realism take the language of science “at face value.”
    • Theoretical terms (planet, electron, neutrino, etc.) are treated as purporting to refer to real entities.
    • No reinterpretation or instrumentalist “fiction” about language is needed.
  • Epistemic disagreement with realists:
    • Realist: we should believe theories are (at least approximately) true.
    • CE: we should withhold belief in the truth of theories about the unobservable. We need belief only in their empirical adequacy.
  • Definition:
    • A theory T is empirically adequate iff everything T says about observable entities, events, and regularities—past, present, and future—is true (i.e.
      it saves the phenomena).
    • Truth about unobservables is unnecessary.
    • Thus, the aim of science = empirical adequacy, not truth.

Observable vs. Unobservable

  • Observable: objects & properties accessible to unaided human senses (or, in some stricter versions, those we could in principle see without theoretical assumptions).
    • Example: mineral hardness, melting point, visible color.
  • Unobservable: atoms, electrons, protons, molecular structures, atomic numbers, quarks, DNA’s exact atomic geometry, etc.
    • Gold’s atomic number: 79 (defined via number of protons/electrons) → unseen by the naked eye; learned through theory-laden instrumentation.

Role of Scientific Models

  • Scientists build idealized, abstract models to represent phenomena. CE stresses:
    • Models are tools for calculation, explanation, and prediction—not literal pictures of reality.
    • Adequacy criterion = match with observable data.
  • Examples discussed:
    1. Crystal lattice models of minerals
    • Colored balls & sticks indicate atomic/molecular arrangement.
    • Useful for predicting cleavage planes, combination tendencies, etc.
    • Do not guarantee truth about actual atomic shapes or bonds.
    1. Stick-and-ball double helix model of DNA
    • Requires multiple idealizations:
      • Perfectly spherical atoms of uniform color.
      • Vacuum-like environment (ignores messy cellular context).
      • Picked-out right- or left-hand helix orientation.
    • Explanatory and pedagogical power despite idealized distortions.

Historical & Philosophical Context

  • Ancient Greek astronomy (“save the phenomena”): Ptolemy & Simplicius accepted that human models can at best fit appearances; only the divine mind could know underlying truth.
    • Post-Galileo era removed theological basis; modern CE’s reasons are different: metaphysics & model idealization.
  • Metaphysical prudence argument:
    • Believing in current unobservables is a high-risk strategy; past science is littered with abandoned entities:
    • \text{Ether}, \text{Phlogiston}, \text{Caloric}, epicycles, etc.
    • Electrons, protons, neutrinos, DNA, etc. might meet the same fate in a century.
    • Therefore we should not incur excess metaphysical commitments.
  • Darwinian/Selectionist explanation of success:
    • Competing theories undergo a “struggle for survival.”
    • The ones we keep are those that fit observational evidence; survival ≠ truth.
    • This provides an alternative explanation to the realist’s “they work because they’re true.”

Idealization, Abstraction, and Model-Based Science (last ~30 yrs of philosophy of science)

  • Growing literature documents that:
    • All theories deploy simplifications, ideal boundary conditions, deliberate omissions.
    • Even if a model is approximately true in a very narrow sense, it is literally false in many respects.
    • Thus, truth may be a misguided or excessively ambitious goal for everyday scientific practice.

Implications & Debates

  • CE offers a middle way:
    • Accept the realist’s sophisticated mathematics, large-scale experimentation, and literal syntax of theory.
    • Reject the necessity of belief in the unseen.
  • Challenges posed to realism:
    1. Pessimistic meta-induction: track record of discarded entities suggests caution.
    2. Underdetermination: multiple empirically adequate theories can exist; why privilege one as true?
  • Realist responses (not in transcript but contextually linked):
    • No-miracle argument: best explanation of reliability/prediction is that theories are at least approximately true.
    • Explaining novel success often seems to require belief in underlying structure.
  • CE counters: “empirical adequacy + selectionist success” is explanation enough; metaphysical humility preferred.

Key Takeaways & Study Reminders

  • Memorize empirical adequacy definition.
  • Distinguish clearly between semantic (language-meaning) vs. epistemic (belief-justification) aspects.
  • Know why CE can accept everyday scientific practice yet remain anti-realist.
  • Be ready to illustrate with examples (gold atomic number 79, crystal models, DNA helix) why observable/unobservable divide matters.
  • Understand why idealization undermines straightforward truth claims.
  • Recall meta-arguments: Darwinian survival of theories, metaphysical risk.
  • Recognize CE’s lineage: from ancient “save the phenomena” to van Fraassen’s modern empiricist stance.