Note
0.0
(0)
Rate it
Take a practice test
Chat with Kai
undefined Flashcards
0 Cards
0.0
(0)
Explore Top Notes
The pearl vocabulary, by John Steinbeck. All chapters (copy)
Note
Studied by 1 person
5.0
(1)
APUSH Entrance Ticket Notes - Semester 1
Note
Studied by 150 people
5.0
(1)
Chapter 6: DNA Quantitation
Note
Studied by 9 people
5.0
(1)
Lecture 1: Intro to Business
Note
Studied by 3 people
5.0
(1)
Two-Sided Limits, Squeeze Theorem, and L'Hopital's Rule
Note
Studied by 142 people
5.0
(1)
Chap 4: States of Consciousness
Note
Studied by 34 people
5.0
(2)
Home
Critical Reasoning 1.3 – Deduction and Induction
Critical Reasoning 1.3 – Deduction and Induction
Course Policy & Disclaimer
All lecture materials are produced and published exclusively for the educational purposes of Yonsei University.
Redistribution to anyone not enrolled in the course is prohibited.
Violation entails legal responsibility.
The Turkey Vulture Example & Competing Theories of Truth
Empirical fact presented:
The turkey vulture gets its name because its red, feather-less head resembles that of a wild turkey (photo credit: reddit link).
Key questions posed:
Can facts be knowledge-dependent?
Can a statement’s truth depend on interpretation?
Two theories of truth highlighted:
Truth-correspondence (adopted for the class)
A statement is true if it accurately corresponds to the world.
Example: If the naming origin of turkey vultures really involves their head’s resemblance, the statement is true by correspondence.
Truth-coherence
Truth hinges on consistency/entailment relations among propositions.
A proposition is true iff it coheres (is entailed by) a consistent web of propositions.
Under coherence, the turkey-vulture fact could be rejected if inconsistent with one’s overall proposition-set.
Warnings against “bullshit” and “bald-faced lies”
These approaches bypass truth entirely, encouraging belief without regard to any theory of truth.
Ethical advice: avoid such thinking regardless of your preferred truth theory.
Session Objectives
Understand key differences between deductive and inductive inferences.
Identify and comprehend common forms of each inference type.
Comparing Two Argument Cases
Assumption: premises are true in both cases.
Case 1 – Inductive (fish):
\text{P1) } Both sharks and goldfish are kinds of fish.
\text{P2) } Sharks are carnivorous.
\text{C) } Therefore, goldfish are probably carnivorous.
Only probable support; other conclusions remain possible.
Case 2 – Deductive (mongoose):
\text{P1) } The meerkat is a member of the mongoose family.
\text{P2) } All members of the mongoose family are omnivores.
\text{C) } Therefore, it necessarily follows that the meerkat is an omnivore.
100 % support; impossible for conclusion to be false if premises are true.
Deduction vs Induction: Definitions & Inferential Strength
Inductive inference:
Conclusion is claimed to
probably
follow from premises.
Inferential claim: “Given true premises, it is highly improbable that the conclusion is false.”
Deductive inference:
Conclusion is claimed to
necessarily
follow from premises.
Inferential claim: “Given true premises, it is logically impossible that the conclusion is false.”
Note: Arguments merely
claim
this strength; many fail in practice but still count as arguments.
Determining Argument Type
1. Linguistic Indicators (helpful but not foolproof)
Deductive cues: necessarily, certainly, absolutely, definitely, must, cannot but…
Inductive cues: probably, likely, plausibly, reasonably, it follows that …
Caveat example:
“Tom is 99 and in a coma, so absolutely he cannot finish the marathon tomorrow.”
Despite ‘absolutely,’ it is still
logically
possible he finishes; thus argument is only inductive.
2. Strength of Inferential Link
Core diagnostic: Does the conclusion
have to
be true (deductive) or just
tend to
be true (inductive) if premises are true?
3. Argument Forms (useful structural clues)
Deductive Forms
Argument based on mathematics
“2 apples + 3 oranges ⇒ at least 5 pieces of fruit.” (2+3=5)
Argument from definition
“Their speech was concise, so it was brief but comprehensive.”
Categorical syllogism (uses "All, some, no")
“All humans are mortal. Prof Gregg is human. ∴ Prof Gregg is mortal.”
Hypothetical syllogism (if … then …)
“If you get an A in logic, then you get a new iPhone. You got an A. ∴ You get a new iPhone.”
Disjunctive syllogism (either … or …)
“Either Larry is in Sincheon or Songdo. He’s not in Sincheon. ∴ He’s in Songdo.”
Fantasy example stressing form, not truth:
\text{P1) } All fairies can fly.
\text{P2) } Ferdinand is a fairy.
\text{C) } Ferdinand can fly.
Deductive &
valid
(truth of premises is separate issue; soundness covered later).
Inductive Forms
Prediction (past → future)
Stock-market & weather-forecast examples (e.g., max 32^\circ C predicted for Sept 2, 3 pm).
Argument from analogy
“Junyeol’s Hyundai Sonata gets great mileage, so yours will too.” (Similarity: same car model.)
Generalization (sample → population)
“Three oranges from crate were tasty ⇒ all oranges in crate are tasty.”
Argument from authority
“H-P earnings will rise; an investment counselor said so.”
Commercial: “Georgia Craft coffee is good because actor Daniel Henney said so.”
Argument based on signs
Road sign shows sharp turns ⇒ road will indeed have sharp turns.
Causal inference
Cause→effect: Watermelon left in freezer overnight ⇒ watermelon is frozen.
Effect→cause: Gate bent & pigeon sitting ⇒ pigeon’s weight bent gate.
Scientific Reasoning & Popper’s Falsificationism
Science employs both inductive and deductive arguments depending on goal.
Inductive in Science: Discovery of Laws
Example: Measuring fall times → notice t \propto \sqrt{d} ⇒ generalize law of falling-body times.
Deductive in Science: Applying Known Laws
Example: Boyle’s law P \propto \frac{1}{V}
Halve gas volume ⇒ pressure doubles.
Though future-oriented, inference is deductive (law applies universally to the case).
Karl Popper’s Normative Claim: Falsification > Confirmation
Good science should attempt to
refute
hypotheses via rigorous testing.
Ideal test follows modus tollens structure: \text{P1) } P \rightarrow Q \ \text{P2) } \neg Q \ \therefore \neg P
If hypothesis predicts result Q, but ¬Q occurs ⇒ hypothesis rejected.
Contrast with confirmation/affirming-the-consequent fallacy:
\text{P1) } P \rightarrow Q \
\text{P2) } Q \
\therefore P \quad (\text{Invalid})
Popper’s demarcation:
A theory is scientific if it exposes itself to possible empirical falsification.
Marxism & psychoanalysis criticized as unfalsifiable ("reinforced dogmatism").
Popper concedes that non-scientific theories can still be insightful.
Misconceptions & Additional Caveats
Do
not
use “specific→general” versus “general→specific” as shortcut:
Inductive can move general→specific (emerald color example).
Deductive can move specific→general (prime-number list ⇒ all odds 2-8 are prime) or specific→specific (Flo the fish example).
Indicators are helpful but insufficient; always test the actual logical relationship.
Exercises Prompt
Students pair up; each pair assigned a question on section 1.3.
5 minutes to develop answer and justification.
Class review follows.
Note
0.0
(0)
Rate it
Take a practice test
Chat with Kai
undefined Flashcards
0 Cards
0.0
(0)
Explore Top Notes
The pearl vocabulary, by John Steinbeck. All chapters (copy)
Note
Studied by 1 person
5.0
(1)
APUSH Entrance Ticket Notes - Semester 1
Note
Studied by 150 people
5.0
(1)
Chapter 6: DNA Quantitation
Note
Studied by 9 people
5.0
(1)
Lecture 1: Intro to Business
Note
Studied by 3 people
5.0
(1)
Two-Sided Limits, Squeeze Theorem, and L'Hopital's Rule
Note
Studied by 142 people
5.0
(1)
Chap 4: States of Consciousness
Note
Studied by 34 people
5.0
(2)