(1) If the sovereign could break a covenant, then it must be with either a multitude or a single person.
(2) The sovereign cannot break a covenant with a multitude.
(3) The sovereign cannot break a covenant with a single person.
(4) Thus, the sovereign cannot break a covenant with either a multitude or a single person.
(5) Therefore, the sovereign cannot break a covenant.
Reasoning
Hobbes’ premise states that all parties to a covenant with the sovereign are either individuals or multitudes, eliminating the existence of another sovereign.
A multitude cannot break a covenant as they lack a unified entity to represent a single will (only an organized group can make a covenant).
Citation from Hobbes: “yet they are not one person.”
Regarding a single person, Hobbes provides two main justifications for why a sovereign cannot break a covenant:
The sovereign has the authority to act on behalf of the individual, thus making any agreement with the individual a non-breach of covenant.
There exists no adjudicator to resolve disputes between the sovereign and the person; hence, the sovereign's judgment prevails by default.
Background on Rousseau
Rousseau’s Life
Born 1712, passed 1778, French Enlightenment thinker.
Experienced a difficult childhood, nurtured by Madame de Warens.
Self-taught in music, philosophy, and classics.
Key Works:
First Discourse (1750): Explores the impact of the restoration of the sciences and the arts on moral character.
Second Discourse (1754): Investigates the origins of inequality among men and its justification by natural law.
Social Contract: His exploration into social structures that are often critiqued for their inequalities.
Investigation into Inequality
General Inquiry: Assessing inequality particularly within social contexts.
Methodology:
Part 1: Motivation and Methodology
Part 2: Stages of Development
Part 3: Evaluating Rousseau's stance on inequality.
The State of Nature
Different Philosophers' Views:
Hobbes: State of nature breeds survival instincts leading to violence.
Key motives include competition, diffidence, and glory.
Resulting condition is solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.
Locke: Views the state of nature as real, emphasizing natural rights.
Rousseau: Acknowledges the hypothetical nature of the state of nature, focusing on its moral implications rather than its factual occurrence.
Human Nature in the State of Nature
Physical Properties:
Humans rely solely on their own bodies; strong, powerful, and healthy.
Mental Properties:
Limited desires focused only on physical needs; lacking long-term planning and language.
Despite this simplicity, Rousseau argues for a "faculty of self-perfection” available to all human beings.
Stages of Development According to Rousseau
Pure State of Nature: Individuals are independent, without social interaction or moral concepts, driven solely by self-preservation and pity.
Elementary Cooperation: Individuals start to recognize the benefits of coordinating actions, albeit without established families or structured interactions.
Family Period: Introduction of families and division of labor due to advancements in technology.
Complex Cooperation: Organizations of greater complexity emerge, resulting in inequality through property and further social conflict.
State of War: Rising tensions between the rich and poor lead to conflict and social structure degradation.
Political Society: Rich individuals band together under social contracts to maintain control but risk creating oppressive systems that ultimately diminish true freedom.
Questions Raised by Rousseau
Is natural inequality justified by natural law?
Rousseau asserts it is a predictable outcome of social interaction but not an inherent condition.
Is good governance achievable?
He implies human nature has flexibility in contrast to Hobbes and Locke’s views.
Inequality's depiction in modern contexts:
Consider statistical data on income disparities in recent decades to evaluate relevance in contemporary society.