Detailed Study Notes on Paternalism and Autonomy
Paternalism and Autonomy
Definition of Paternalism
- Interfering with a person's liberty of action.
- Reasons for interference:
- To benefit them.
- To make them better off in the long run.
Examples of Paternalism
- Parent to child control: Parents make decisions for their children, believing it's in the child's best interest.
- Medical scenarios: Stepping in for someone with conditions like dementia who can't make informed decisions.
- Legal and Governmental examples:
- Taking kids out of a neglectful home.
- Seat belt laws: Mandating seat belt usage despite some people's objections.
- Cell phone usage laws: While partly about preventing harm to others, they also protect the user.
- Taxes on smoking: Discouraging smoking for the benefit of individuals, despite objections from smokers.
Libertarianism vs. Paternalism
- Libertarianism: Holds that paternalism in any form is wrong.
- Dominant View: Seeks a balance between individual control over one's destiny and allowing outside intervention in certain cases.
- Middle-of-the-road View: Most people lean towards a middle ground, but the exact point on the spectrum is debatable.
Onora O'Neill's Approach
- Paternalism is sometimes justified when individuals have diminished capacity to reason.
- The default position is that adults have the right to make their own decisions.
- Considerations about paternalism should be based on the variable and partial character of actual human autonomy.
- Human autonomy is affected by:
- Emotions.
- Information availability.
- Reasoning abilities, statistically and logically.
- Autonomy exists on a sliding scale, influenced by capabilities, knowledge, and emotional state.
Fundamental Values in Medical Concern
Autonomy
- If autonomy is the fundamental value, it justifies respecting patients and their wishes.
- Problem: Some individuals lack autonomy (e.g., unconscious patients, children, dementia patients).
- If autonomy is missing, it doesn't justify treating the person with any respect, which leads to issues such as doing medical experiments on comatose patients.
Beneficence
- Definition: Doing good for someone, taking care of their interests.
- Problem: If beneficence is the fundamental value, it disregards the importance of autonomy.
- Autonomy and degrees of autonomy should influence how patients are treated.
Result-Oriented Ethics (Consequentialism, Utilitarianism)
- Synonyms: Result oriented ethics, consequentialism.
- Utilitarianism: Autonomy matters only if it affects the outcome.
- Beneficence outweighs autonomy in result-oriented ethics. The goal is to maximize overall well-being.
- Paternalism is only misplaced when it reflects miscalculation of benefits, but if the intentions are pure the action is acceptable.
- Utilitarians value autonomy and positive character traits conditionally, as long as they contribute to good outcomes.
John Stuart Mill's Utilitarian Justification for Autonomy
- Each person is best informed about their own life, resources, capabilities, and happiness.
- Paternalism is often a miscalculation because individuals are better judges of their own happiness.
Problems with Mill's View
- Lack of evidence that individuals always make the best decisions for themselves.
- Analysis paralysis: Too many options can overwhelm individuals, leading to poor decisions.
- Even if Mill is correct, autonomy only "tends" to be better, without a rock-solid guarantee.
- Utilitarianism may still override autonomy if calculations suggest a better outcome by doing said override.
O'Neill's View on Result-Oriented Ethics
- Result-oriented ethics cannot adequately justify the importance of autonomy.
Action-Oriented Ethics (Deontological Ethics)
- Focuses on intentional action.
- Autonomy is a necessary condition for deliberation and action.
- Autonomy is crucial for having value, dignity, and being praiseworthy or blameworthy, so respect is always due.
Problem with Deontological Ethics
- Some people lack autonomy, but this shouldn't mean they lack respect or that anything is acceptable to do to them.
- Deontology can’t allow for mistreatment of people lacking autonomy.
O'Neill's Modification to Action-Oriented Ethics
- Respect the fact that some patients lack some features of autonomy while still having others.
- Allow for partial autonomy.
- Instead of an ideal model of autonomy and consent, opt for a partial and actual model.
- Account for the varying levels of rationale, reasoning ability, and awareness of consequences.
Ideal vs. Actual Consent and Autonomy
Ideal Model
- Based on what someone would agree to if they were a fully informed, rational reasoner.
- Every person has a "best self" that is fully informed and capable of optimal reasoning.
Problems with the Ideal Model
- Can justify paternalism because it disregards the actual patient's compromised reasoning.
- The ideal reasoner would agree to things that the actual patient might not, leading to overriding the patient's wishes.
- Ideal conditions need to be met in order for a person to be autonomous.
Actual Model
- Base concern for patients on their actual capabilities for consent and autonomy.
- Determine when actual consent is genuine and significant versus spurious or misleading.
O'Neill's Belief
- Make it possible for patients to consent by:
- Bringing patients up to speed.
- Explaining information in an understandable way.
- The messiness of this approach doesn't bother her.
- Concern for medical autonomy is centered upon the patient, not the doctor.
- Patients need to be able to accept or reject proposals.
*Medical practice respects patient autonomy when it allows patients, as they actually are, to refuse or accept what is proposed to them.
- The ways in which human autonomy is limited are highly varied.
- Established procedures cannot absolutely guarantee genuine consent.
End User License Agreements
- Nobody reads end user license agreements, and they frequently do not hold up in court.
- Consent forms might be routinized, but they cannot ensure that everyone who signs has legitimately consented.
- Verbal consent, power of attorney, can embody compromised interest which violates what the patient would want even if the legal requirements are met.
Consent and Consequences
Limiting Consent
- It is impossible to consent to all possible consequences.
- Focus on the fundamental stuff in policy.
- Patients should be in a position to agree or disagree with what is happening to them.
- Trivial and ancillary aspects of action proposals may not need formalized consent.
Coercion and Deception
General Prohibition
- Coercion and deception prevent legitimate consent, even for ideal reasoners.
- Misinformation or forcing a decision invalidates consent.
Fundamental vs. Non-Fundamental
- Coercion and deception about the fundamental stuff is off limits.
- Doctors may be allowed to coerce or deceive about non-fundamental aspects.
Examples
- Placebos: Deception about inert pills can have powerful effects.
- Restraining a patient: Coercion may be necessary but not fundamental to the procedure. It may be necessary to avoid patients flinching.
Questions and Concerns
Fundamental Definition
- The question of what constitutes "fundamental" is raised.
- It is up for debate whether fundamental is what a doctor or patient understand to be of fundamental importance.
Perspective Matters
- Blood transfusions can be standard for doctors but violate religious beliefs of patients.
- Perspective may be the defining factor in determining whether a component of a proposed medical procedure is "fundamental" or not.
Summary
- Actions of the goals of medical practice have to serve what the patient's aims are.
- Our goals have to be considered when we're talking about the difference between paternalism and non-paternalistic practice.
O'Neill's Final Proposal
Summary
- Medical practice should assess autonomy on a case-by-case basis.
- Autonomy should be made possible for patients whenever practical.
Potential Drawbacks
- This approach might be impractical due to the amount of work required.
- Standard procedures, despite their flaws, might be the best compromise.