If autonomy is missing, it doesn't justify treating the person with any respect, which leads to issues such as doing medical experiments on comatose patients.
Beneficence
Definition: Doing good for someone, taking care of their interests.
Problem: If beneficence is the fundamental value, it disregards the importance of autonomy.
Autonomy and degrees of autonomy should influence how patients are treated.
Synonyms: Result oriented ethics, consequentialism.
Utilitarianism: Autonomy matters only if it affects the outcome.
Beneficence outweighs autonomy in result-oriented ethics. The goal is to maximize overall well-being.
Paternalism is only misplaced when it reflects miscalculation of benefits, but if the intentions are pure the action is acceptable.
Utilitarians value autonomy and positive character traits conditionally, as long as they contribute to good outcomes.
John Stuart Mill's Utilitarian Justification for Autonomy
Each person is best informed about their own life, resources, capabilities, and happiness.
Paternalism is often a miscalculation because individuals are better judges of their own happiness.
Problems with Mill's View
Lack of evidence that individuals always make the best decisions for themselves.
Analysis paralysis: Too many options can overwhelm individuals, leading to poor decisions.
Even if Mill is correct, autonomy only "tends" to be better, without a rock-solid guarantee.
Utilitarianism may still override autonomy if calculations suggest a better outcome by doing said override.
O'Neill's View on Result-Oriented Ethics
Result-oriented ethics cannot adequately justify the importance of autonomy.
Action-Oriented Ethics (Deontological Ethics)
Focuses on intentional action.
Autonomy is a necessary condition for deliberation and action.
Autonomy is crucial for having value, dignity, and being praiseworthy or blameworthy, so respect is always due.
Problem with Deontological Ethics
Some people lack autonomy, but this shouldn't mean they lack respect or that anything is acceptable to do to them.
Deontology can’t allow for mistreatment of people lacking autonomy.
O'Neill's Modification to Action-Oriented Ethics
Respect the fact that some patients lack some features of autonomy while still having others.
Allow for partial autonomy.
Instead of an ideal model of autonomy and consent, opt for a partial and actual model.
Account for the varying levels of rationale, reasoning ability, and awareness of consequences.
Ideal vs. Actual Consent and Autonomy
Ideal Model
Based on what someone would agree to if they were a fully informed, rational reasoner.
Every person has a "best self" that is fully informed and capable of optimal reasoning.
Problems with the Ideal Model
Can justify paternalism because it disregards the actual patient's compromised reasoning.
The ideal reasoner would agree to things that the actual patient might not, leading to overriding the patient's wishes.
Ideal conditions need to be met in order for a person to be autonomous.
Actual Model
Base concern for patients on their actual capabilities for consent and autonomy.
Determine when actual consent is genuine and significant versus spurious or misleading.
O'Neill's Belief
Make it possible for patients to consent by:
Bringing patients up to speed.
Explaining information in an understandable way.
The messiness of this approach doesn't bother her.
Concern for medical autonomy is centered upon the patient, not the doctor.
Patients need to be able to accept or reject proposals.
*Medical practice respects patient autonomy when it allows patients, as they actually are, to refuse or accept what is proposed to them.
Formalizing Consent
Impossibility of Formalization
The ways in which human autonomy is limited are highly varied.
Established procedures cannot absolutely guarantee genuine consent.
End User License Agreements
Nobody reads end user license agreements, and they frequently do not hold up in court.
Consent Forms
Consent forms might be routinized, but they cannot ensure that everyone who signs has legitimately consented.
Verbal consent, power of attorney, can embody compromised interest which violates what the patient would want even if the legal requirements are met.
Consent and Consequences
Limiting Consent
It is impossible to consent to all possible consequences.
Focus on the fundamental stuff in policy.
Patients should be in a position to agree or disagree with what is happening to them.
Trivial and ancillary aspects of action proposals may not need formalized consent.
Coercion and Deception
General Prohibition
Coercion and deception prevent legitimate consent, even for ideal reasoners.
Misinformation or forcing a decision invalidates consent.
Fundamental vs. Non-Fundamental
Coercion and deception about the fundamental stuff is off limits.
Doctors may be allowed to coerce or deceive about non-fundamental aspects.
Examples
Placebos: Deception about inert pills can have powerful effects.
Restraining a patient: Coercion may be necessary but not fundamental to the procedure. It may be necessary to avoid patients flinching.
Questions and Concerns
Fundamental Definition
The question of what constitutes "fundamental" is raised.
It is up for debate whether fundamental is what a doctor or patient understand to be of fundamental importance.
Perspective Matters
Blood transfusions can be standard for doctors but violate religious beliefs of patients.
Perspective may be the defining factor in determining whether a component of a proposed medical procedure is "fundamental" or not.
Summary
Actions of the goals of medical practice have to serve what the patient's aims are.
Our goals have to be considered when we're talking about the difference between paternalism and non-paternalistic practice.
O'Neill's Final Proposal
Summary
Medical practice should assess autonomy on a case-by-case basis.
Autonomy should be made possible for patients whenever practical.
Potential Drawbacks
This approach might be impractical due to the amount of work required.
Standard procedures, despite their flaws, might be the best compromise.