Aesthetics
What kinds of question are we asking when we questions of aesthetics?
What is beauty?
How do we know what is beauty?
How/can we create the beautiful?
Is the beautiful true?
Is the beautiful good?
Is the beautiful real?
Beauty
“Commonly defined as a characteristic present in objects, such as nature, work, and a human person, that provides a perceptual experience of pleasure, joy, and satisfaction to the observer
The birth of Aesthetics
Alexander Baumgarten (1714-1762) coined the term aesthetics
For Baumgarten the purpose of art is to produce beauty
Beauty is:
Best found in nature
Art is an imitation of nature
Rewind to the Ancients
Aesthetics was not its own realm
Greek philosophy was oriented towards eudaimonia
Beauty was ordered to the good
The ultimate good pointed toward the divine
Beauty has an objective components
Connected to mathematics and therefore order, unity, and balance
Plato
Thinks things like beauty, good, justice have ideal, eternal forms
These are divine
Beauty exists in the realm of the gods, imperfectly replicated in the material realm
Sharp divide between the material and immaterial realm
Truth, beauty, and goodness go together
Not a fan of the artists and poets
Augustine (354-430) and Aquinas (1225-1274)
Maintained the unity of truth, beauty, and goodness
God is the final end
Augustine’s view of virtues
Aquinas’s beatitude (friendship with God)
The birth of Aesthetics
Alexander Baumgarten (1714-1762) coined the term aesthetics
The focus will shift to art away from beauty
Modern Developments
Hume
Did not like the idea that beauty was the result of unexamined custom
He though there would be correct and incorrect judgements about what is beautiful
Kant
Beauty evoke love without desire
Beauty is entirely disinterested
Beauty is non-intrumental (good regardless of its usefulness)
Nature is beautiful because it looks like art, but all art is artificial because it is just a representation
Schopenhauer
Art is not beautiful because it imitates nature
Art attempts to give us a picture of a universal rather than a particular
Subjective an Objective Elements of Beauty
Ancients and Medieval Christians largely saw beauty as objective
It derived front the divine realm
Beauty is that which is enchanted?
Moderns emphasize the role of the subject beholding the object in the role of beauty
Moral Beauty
Ancients and Christians see beauty and morality as interwinded
Leo Tolstoy (Russian author 1828-1910) though art can only be good if it has a moral purpose
It should inject moral emotions
Neitzsche (1844-1900) though art and morality were distinct and art was supreme
20th century ethos is that art can be great while morally deleterious
Arguments
Logic is a discipline used to differentiate good arguments from bad
Inductive and deductive are different forms of logic
Statements are claims that can either be true or false
An argument is a sequence of statements
The lasting claim in a sequence in the conclusion are called conclusions
Statements in support of the conclusion are called premises
Every argument has a premise, so it is not a flaw to ed an argument to not have argued for the premises
Valid and Invalid Arguments
Valid arguments - if the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true
True premises, true conclusion
Example
Premise: all biologists are scientists
Premise: John is not a scientists
Conclusion: John is not a biologist
Valid arguments can have
False premises, false conclusion
Example:
Premise: all humans are plants
Premise: John is a human
Conclusion: John is a plant
Valid arguments can have
False premises, true conclusion
Example
Premise: all dogs are humans
Premise: John is a dog
Conclusion: John is a human
But deductive valid arguments cannot have
True premises and a false conclusion
The question at hand with valid/invalid arguments is whether the form of the argument is good, not its content
When we speak of formal validity, it is our focus
Since arguments forms are structure distinct from argument content, we can easily signify different forms by using letters to represent statements in the argument
If p, the q
p
Therefore p
Common Forms: Hypothetical/Conditional
Some of the more common arguments patterns that you encounter are deductive, and they contain one or more conditional, of if-then, premises
The first statement in a conditional premise (the if part) is know as the antecedent
The second part (then part) is know as the consequent
A syllogism is a deductive argument made up of three statements- two premises and a conclusion
Common Forms: Modus Ponens
Modus ponens
If P then Q
P
Therefore, Q
Example
If the job is worth doing, then it’s worth doing well
The job is worth doing
Therefore, it’s worth doing well
Common Forms: Modus Tollens
Modus tollens
If P then Q
Not P
Therefore, Q
Example
If it’s raining, the park is closed
The park is not closes
Therefore, it’s not raining
Common Forms: Disjunctive Syllogism
Disjunctive syllogism
Either P or Q
Not P
Therefore, Q
Example
Either Ralph walked the dog, or he stayed home
He didn’t walk the dog
Therefore, he stayed home
Common Forms: Hypothetical Syllogism
Hypothetical syllogism
If P then Q
If Q then R
Therefore, if P then R
Example
If the ball drops, the lever turns to the right
If the lever turns to the right, the engine will stop
Therefore, if the ball drops, the engine will stop
Common Invalid Forms: Denying the Antecedent
Denying the antecedent
If P then Q
Not P
Therefore, not Q (this is not a valid argument)
Example
If Einstein invented the steam engine, then he’s a great scientists
Einstein did not invent the steam engine
Therefore, Einstein is not a great scientist
Commons Invalid Forms: Affirming the Consequent
Affirming the consequent
If P then Q
Q
Therefore, P (this is not a valid argument)
Example
If Springfield is the capital of Missouri, then it is in Missouri
Springfield is in Missouri
Therefore, Springfield is the capital of Missouri
The Limits of Logic
If two things are indistinguishable by ordinary means, the if one is red, so it the other
The one is red
Therefore, so is the other
The result means that you might have a bright yellow tile that through a modus ponens (the valid argument) leads to an absurd conclusion
Arguments that are valid can be bad arguments
They might be circular
God exists
Therefore, God exists
Premises must be believable independent of the conclusion
God knows when you will die
Therefore, God exists
Provided a premise that requires believing the conclusion is begging the questions
In other words, an argument that demand that you first ask another, different question is not question begging
You can have arguments that are non-demostrative (not valid) but are still good arguments
For instance, strong inductive arguments are good arguments even though they are not deductively valid
The sun rises every morning, therefore the sum will rise tomorrow
Inferences to the best explanation are an example of good non-demonstrative arguments
When you begin with a group of settled facts and reason backwards to a theory that best explains them
Philosophy of Religion
What do we mean by God?
How philosophy and faith can relate
Conflict
Compartmental
Convergence
Topics
Arguments about God
The ontological argument
The cosmological argument
The argument for design
The moral argument
Rebuttals
The problem of evil
Having proof and basic beliefs
The Ontological Argument
Anselm of Canterbury (1033-1109)
God is the greatest conceivable being
God has all possible perfections
Existence is a perfection
God has the property of existence
Therefore, God exists
Premises one and two are simply statin the definition of the GCB
This is an a priori argument
Premise three and four
Aquinas think this is like saying God’s existence is self evident
Gaunilo’s objection - you can’t move from an idea of something to it’s reality
Kant does not think that existence is a real predicate
Does this argument prove God’s existence?
What did Anselm thinks this argument did?
Anselm was a theologian, the first of the scholastic theologians
Theology is “faith seeking understanding” or rather he says, “I believe in order that I may understand”
We don’t believe only to experience but also to understand
Anselm’s goal was not to discover reasons to believe but the reasons for what we already believe
Reason is not sought as a pre-requisite or in order to make faith more certain but to make faith more understandable
Human reason is not bad
1 Peter 3 - always be prepared…
Human reason is given by God, so it is dependent on God
Attempting to prove God is a practice in the mind taking the shape of the heart’s love for God
The questions here are not epistemic in the way that we assume as moderns
The Cosmological Argument
One of the more famous versions of this comes from Thomas Aquinas
Aquinas though that knowledge of God should be made available in the most obvious way, namely his effects
This is an empirical argument
It asks, what is the best explanation for the existence of anything in the world? Why is there something rather than nothing?
The answer, like Anselm’s, is theological
Aquinas’s Five Ways (or five things in the world that prove “what everyone understand to be God”)
The reality of motion, efficient causes, contingent beings, morality, and design
Multiple version of the cosmological argument
For instance, Kalam’s (repeated by early Christian theologians and used by Jewish and Muslim thinker as well)
This is a valid deductive argument
Whatever beings to exist has a cause
The universe began to exist
Therefore, the universe has a cause
Recent scientific consensus around the fact that the earth has a “start date” has made premise two even more trustworthy
If true, this argument out naturalism/materialism and nontheistic religions
It established a “transcendent, personal, immaterial, necessary, and singular cause of the universe”
This is not specifically the Christian God, but it is consistent with him
Objections
Aquinas state, “this cannot go on the infinity, because then there would be no first mover, and consequently, no other mover, seeing that subsequent movers only inasmuch as they are moved by the first mover”
In other worlds, Aquinas rules out the possibility of an infinite regress
This has been challenged as an unwarranted assumption
Samuel Clarke (1675-1729) leaves open the possibility for an infinite regress and reworks the argument accordingly
Dependent being - anything whose reason for existence is outside itself
Independent being - anything that has a reason for existence inside itself
Clarke’s argument takes the form of a reductio ad absurdum
A
If A, then B
If A, then not B
Therefore, not A
Suppose there is nothing but an infinite causal regress of dependent beings, or an ICRDB for short
There must be some explanation of the existence of the entire ICRDB
That explanation can’t exist outside of the ICRDB
Nor can that explanation exist inside of the ICRDB
So, the ICRSB exists without any explanation at all
This contradicts the second premise
Therefore, the supposition in premise 1 must be false
David Hume objects to premise two
He argues you can have reasons for all the individual items in a system without needing an explanation for the whole
Hume’s principle - “once you have explained the properties of each element in a totality, you have explained that features of the totality as well”
The Argument from Morality
The argument from morality can be displayed as such
If God does not exist, there are no objective moral properties
Objective moral properties exist
Therefore, God exists
The old atheists think that this argument is correct, but they do not agree with the conclusion
They attack premise two
The old atheists
Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900)
Nietzsche calls ethics a “soporific device”… in other words, having nice moral boxes that you can tough helps you sleep will at night
If we step outside of this delusion and move “beyond good and evil” we recognize that our behavior is only shaped by our will to power
God doesn’t exist, therefore there is no ethics
Bertrand Russell (1872-1970)
He thinks that morality rises and falls with God and that “all we can do…is build out lives on “the firm foundation of unyielding despair”
So, Russell argues that there are no objective moral properties but that moral properties are subjective
The new atheists don’t want to deny moral standards so they try to find other ways of identifying moral standards in the world
One might suggest that when the old atheists “killed God” they understood the gravity of their endeavor
The new atheists (who rarely are commended for their depth or sharpness of thoughts) are more rhetorically oriented
Richard Dawkins, Christopher Hitchens, Sam Harris, and Daniel Dennett
A puzzle about God and morality from Plato’s Euthyphro
In the story Plato writes of Socrates bumping to a man named Euthyphro who claims that morality is that which pleases the gods (a polytheistic context)
One images then the gods or God going through various actions and labeling them moral or immoral
Is the good good because God says it is or does God say it is because it is good
Are the decisions that God makes about morality of an item arbitrary or not?
If they are arbitrary then our morals are based on nothing more than an arbitrary decree?
If they are not arbitrary then the morality is based upon something that is independent of God (i.e., they are moral or immoral and even God must admit that)
This is one way of asking the question, is God murders someone is it still a sin?
The Problem of Evil
This sometimes would be better described as the problem of suffering
In short, if there is a good all-powerful, and all-knowing God who is in charge, why does there seem to be so much suffering in the world?
There are two objections raised here: one logical and one evidential
Responses to the problem of evil are know as theodicies
While not the first, our friend, David Hume, submitted the following argument
The following points are logically inconsistent
God is omnipotent (all-powerful)
God is omniscient (all-knowing)
God is perfectly good
There is evil in the world
The logical problem can be solved saying
One can not that some good things (compassion and empathy) in the world require suffering and are justified
Therefore, a fifth point must be considered
There is no morally sufficient reason for God to allow evil
The argument can be formalized as such
A perfect (all-powerful, all-knowing, all-good) God exists
Evil exists
A perfect God would allow evil only if there were a morally sufficient reason to allow it
There is no morally sufficient reason for God to allow evil
This argument points to the evidentiary problem: namely, the existence of evil may not be a logical problem, but why is there so much suffering in the world?
Jesus is the truth and love. Love and truth go together and sometimes it is not always needed to be logical
A response by Eleanore Stump (1947-)
Based on the Christian traditions and three theological beliefs
Adam fell
Natural evil entered the world as a result of Adam’s fall
After death, depending on their state at the time of their death, either (a) human beings go to heaven or (b) they go to hell
Stump defends these in turn as follows:
Adam fell, which implies three things
Due to humans’ choices their will were altered for the worse
Adam and Eve sin
The alteration involves the nature of human free will
According to Anselm and Aquinas (among others) out wills work in tandem with reason and desire
A truly free will is that “is disposed to will the good consistently/ constantly”
The change of nature in the will is inheritable (passed down)
Humans must be free to make decision of serious consequence
Natural evil entered the world as a result of Adam’s fall
No person suffered from disease, tornados, droughts, etc, until Adam’s fall
She notes she does not need to prove this (or any of their points) by only show they are not demostrably false
After death, depending on their state at the time of their death, either (a) human beings go to heaven or (b) they go to hell
Hell raises a new level of the problem of evil
Stump points to the Christian tradition (such as Dante) and the essence of hell as absence of union with God
She conclude that “everlasting life in hell is the ultimate evil which can befall a person in this world; but the torments of hell are the natural conditions of some persons, and God can spare such persons those pains only by depriving them of their nature or their existence
A response by Eleanore Stump in summary
Adam’s fall created a defect in the will
This inclines human to will what they ought not to
It is not possible for people to go to heaven (be in union with God) while in this condition
Must God try to fix this?
He cannot fix this by using his omnipotence without violating free will
To remove the defect miraculously would force person’s free will to be other than they can be
Even though God is omnipotent, he cannot “directly and miraculously could remove the defect in free will”
Stump does not say that God causes suffering, but the suffering “will be justified it if bring that person nearer to the ultimate good in a way he could not have been without the suffering”
God can help us have the will in order to go the good
We freely choose to be helped by God
The Argument from Design
Seeds of this argument an be seen in Aquinas’s fifth way which points to all things being ordered to a valuable end
The argument runs that the apparent complexity in nature shows there must be a sentient, intelligent designer
William Paley (1743-1805)
You are hiking in the woods and stumble upon a watch, What is the best explanation for that watch?
Like the watch, “the universe…shares marks of intelligence - complexity, order, and purpose - and it is reasonable to think that the universe is the product of intelligent design
The natural world shows considerable complexity and apparent design
The only possible explanation of this complexity and apparent design in the natural world is that the natural world was produces by an intelligent sentient designer
Therefor, there must be an intelligent, sentient designer responsible for the complexity and apparent design in the natural world
Premise one is generally accepted
Some complain that this like having only one opening (through) for water and air is evidence of poor design
Premise two meets more objections
From our friend David Hume…
We cannot infer a single designer..design by committee?
Does the designer need to be the first cause?
If the argument for design works in tandem with the cosmological argument, the it provides evidence of a personal and intelligent cause, rather than proof of the first cause (for that you can refer to the cosmological argument)
Objection based on evolution through natural selection
What responsibilities are possible?
You could look to disprove evolution as a theory
You could hold evolution in tandem with theism
You can change the argument so that the intelligent designer is not the ONLY person possible explanation but the best
Argument for fine-tuning is
The existence of a fine-tuned universe is not surprising under theism
The existence of a fine-tuned universe is enormously surprising under naturalism
Therefore, by the likelihood principle, the existence of a fine-tuned universe strongly supports theism over naturalism
Pascal’s Wager
Blaise Pascal (1623-1662)
Has a transformative mystical experience that brings him to faith and his works tries to wrestle out the defense of this faith
Is known as a historical proponent of fideism
Fideism - the reliance upon faith rather than reason in matters of philosophy and religion
Truth of certain kinds can only be attainted by “foregoing rational inquiry and relying souly on faith”
We cannot know if God exists
For Pascal, “reason will not be enable to decide either way [whether God does or does not exist], or rule out either alternative”
Because “if there is a God, he is infinitely beyond out comprehension, since having neither parts nor limits he bears no relation to us?
The Bet
Deciding if God exists is like guessing heads or tails on a coin flip that is happening at the end of an infinite path/road
But you must bet
There is not neutral position. You are already implicated
Decision theory based upon expected utility
Decision theory based upon expected utility
In the face of having to make a decision and being unable to know for certain, the rational thing to do is to bet on God existing
Objections
If you don’t believe in God, but you think it is rational to bet of God’s existence, how can you force yourself to believe that God exists?
Can you become a believer for purely self-interested reasons?
Does this prove any particular religion or just the irrationality of atheism and agnosticism?
What is the God that exists is perverse and punishes those that are religious rather than rewards them?