Critical Thinking and Ethics Lecture Review
Lecture notes: Evaluating Philosophical and Moral Arguments
Context and course schedule (Module 1: Critical Thinking and Ethics)
- Argument analysis worksheet due Friday at 11:59 PM.
- Wednesday topic: fallacies and biases.
- Monday, Sept 29: Reading Quiz 1 on subjectivism by Julian Driver and egoism and moral skepticism by James Rachel.
- Goal: learn to identify, map, and evaluate arguments; understand what makes an argument strong or weak.
Big-picture motivation
- Critical thinking is underemphasized in many educational systems; modern times push for more careful engagement with issues that matter in daily life.
- Higher education should be a venue for the free exchange of ideas and constructive argumentation, not just assertion.
- The ability to evaluate arguments helps us discern what to believe and how to respond in disagreements, debates, or everyday decisions.
What is an argument? basic definitions
- An argument is a piece of reasoning offered in support of the truth of a claim.
- A claim, or statement, is an assertion that something is the case or is not the case; it can be true or false.
- A standalone question, command, greeting, or exclamation is not an argument.
- In everyday text, arguments can be woven into narrative background information; the argument itself is the reasoning that supports a claim.
- In practice, arguments consist of:
- A main claim (the conclusion),
- One or more supporting claims (premises or reasons).
Key terms: statements, claims, conclusions, premises
- Statement/claim: an assertion that something is or is not the case; can be true or false.
- Conclusion: the main claim that follows from the premises; what the argument is trying to establish.
- Premises: the reasons or supporting claims given for the conclusion.
- Mapping arguments: identify conclusion first, then premises; then check logical connection.
Indicators of premise and conclusion
- Premise indicators (signal that what follows is a reason):
- because, since
- Conclusion indicators (signal that what follows is a conclusion):
- therefore, so
- Important caveats
- The word "so" can be ambiguous; context is needed to determine if it signals a conclusion.
- Practical use: when you see a premise indicator (e.g., "because"), what follows is a reason; when you see a conclusion indicator (e.g., "therefore"), what follows is the conclusion.
Mapping a simple argument (example: slavery)
- Text: "Slavery is wrong because it deprives another human being of the right to freedom."
- Identification:
- Conclusion: Slavery is wrong.
- Premise: It deprives another human being of the right to freedom.
- Alternative ordering:
- Premise: Slavery deprives … of the right to freedom.
- Conclusion: Slavery is wrong. (Introduced by "Therefore" or "So".)
- One-sentence argument: conclusions and premises can appear in the same sentence.
Examples used to illustrate argument structure
- Pepperoni on pizza:
- Premise: Pepperoni makes me sick.
- Conclusion: We should not get pepperoni on the pizza.
- Indicator word: because (tells you what follows is the premise).
- One-sentence form: Pepperoni makes me sick, therefore we should not get pepperoni on the pizza.
- Capital punishment example:
- Premise indicator: because
- Conclusion: Capital punishment is morally permissible.
- Premise: It helps deter crime.
- Mapping shows how conclusions can be at the start or end of a sentence depending on word order.
- Conditional (If–Then) argument:
- If John killed Bill in self defense, then he did not commit murder.
- Premise: John did kill Bill in self defense.
- Conclusion: Therefore, he did not commit murder.
- Important: when mapping, include the if–then clause as part of the premises.
- Sherlock Holmes example (implied premise):
- Explicit premise: The dog did not bark.
- Implied (well-known) premise: Dogs bark at strangers.
- Conclusion: The thief was no stranger to the dog.
- Mapping: Dogs bark at strangers (implied); The dog did not bark (explicit); Therefore, the thief was no stranger to the dog.
- Note: implied premises are often well-supported general facts; you may need to acknowledge them in analysis.
- All pigs can fly example (valid but not sound):
- Premises: All pigs can fly; Anything that can fly can swim.
- Conclusion: Pigs can swim.
- This is logically valid (if premises were true) but not sound because the premises are false.
- Inadequate premises can make a valid argument unsound:
- Example: Cost-effectiveness claim in capital-punishment debate may be false; if a premise is false, the argument remains valid but not sound.
- Invalid argument example (Jill–Jeff–Kathy):
- Premises: Jill loves Jeff; Jeff loves Kathy.
- Conclusion: Jill loves Kathy.
- This is invalid because the conclusion does not logically follow from the premises.
Inductive vs deductive arguments
- Deductive arguments: aim for guaranteed truth of the conclusion if premises are true; validity matters.
- Example: All men are mortal; Socrates is a man; Therefore, Socrates is mortal. (Deductive, valid, and sound.)
- Inductive arguments: aim for probable support; conclusions are likely but not guaranteed.
- Valid vs sound distinction (recap):
- Valid: the conclusion follows logically from the premises (structure only, does not consider truth of premises).
- Sound: the argument is valid and the premises are actually true.
- An argument can be valid but not sound if a premise is false.
- An argument can be invalid even if many premises are true.
Common pitfalls and nuanced points
- Even if the conclusion follows logically, you must assess the truth/acceptability of the premises (often requires evidence or data).
- The presence of an implied premise requires asking whether it is a well-known or established fact.
- A paragraph in a text may be background or narration; the actual argumentative core is the set of statements that support the conclusion.
- One-sentence premises and conclusions are common, but longer arguments have multiple premises and possibly intermediate conclusions.
The steps in analyzing an argument (process from the lecture)
1) Identify the conclusion using conclusion indicator words or strong claims (e.g., a moral obligation, a claim about what is true).
2) Identify the premises (the reasons given in support of the conclusion).
3) Determine if the conclusion follows logically from the premises (the logic condition).- Formally: if the premises were true, would the conclusion necessarily be true?
- Notation: the relationship can be expressed as P1 \,\land\, P2 \,\land\, \dots \,\land\, Pn \rightarrow C or equivalently {P1, P2, \dots, Pn} \models C.
4) Determine if the premises are true or acceptable (often requires research or evidence; some premises require data to verify).
5) Determine if there are any faults in the reasoning (to be explored in the next class: fallacies and biases).
- If you confirm step 3 (logical connection) but step 4 fails (premises are false), the argument is valid but not sound.
- If step 3 fails, the argument is invalid regardless of premises.
Practical exam preparation notes (context for your worksheet)
- Your worksheet will be about identifying the conclusion, identifying premises, and evaluating whether the conclusion follows logically from the premises.
- You will also evaluate the truth/acceptability of the premises and comment on strengths and weaknesses of the argument.
- Expect to encounter a mix of one-sentence arguments and longer, multi-premise arguments; pay attention to premise indicators and conclusion indicators.
The broader goal for your course meetings
- Friday: complete argument analysis worksheet.
- Wednesday: cover fallacies and biases to prepare for deeper analysis.
- Readings ahead: On the quiz, focus on subjectivism and egoism/moral skepticism as assigned.
- Upcoming lectures will finish the current topic and introduce fallacies and biases, then move to new material.
Quick takeaway checklist for evaluating any argument
- Step 1: What is the conclusion? (look for indicators and strong claims)
- Step 2: What are the premises? (the reasons given)
- Step 3: Does the conclusion logically follow from the premises? (logic condition)
- Step 4: Are the premises true/acceptable? (needs evidence or data)
- Step 5: Are there any fallacies or faulty reasoning patterns?
- Remember: an argument can be valid but unsound if a premise is false; it can be sound only if both it is valid and all premises are true.
Final note from the session
- The instructor plans to finish lecture three (philosophical argumentation) and then move to lecture four on fallacies and biases in the next class.
- The argument-analysis portion of the course remains a central focus through the upcoming sessions.
Encourage questions and practice
- If you’re unsure, try mapping an argument you encounter in readings or everyday life by identifying C, P1, P2, etc., and then test logical connection and premise truth.
- Use the if–then form when needed to preserve conditional structures in your maps.
Remember the math/logic notations used here
- Logical entailment form: P1 \,\land\, P2 \,\land\, \dots \,\land\, P_n \rightarrow C
- Logical entailment shorthand: {P1, P2, \dots, P_n} \models C