MJ

How Do Philosophers Arrive at Truth? NOTES

Philosophical Methods of Inquiry

Sources of Evidence

  • Philosophical claims require evidence, even though philosophy isn't an empirical science.

  • Philosophers need reasons for their claims.

History
  • The history of philosophy is a significant source of evidence.

  • Philosophical thinking has origins worldwide from the beginning of recorded history.

  • Historical philosophers, sages, natural philosophers, and religious thinkers offer insights and arguments.

  • Example: The Greeks distinguished between generic terms (cat, tree, house) and specific, individual beings.

  • Philosophical Question: What's the relationship between general terms and specific things?

  • Questions of morality and social organization remain relevant over time.

  • Political leaders often reference historical philosophers (e.g., U.S. Founding Fathers, Confucius in China).

Intuition
  • Intuition, in a philosophical sense, traces back to Plato and involves insight into the nature of things.

  • Rene Descartes' definition: "the conception of a clear and attentive mind, which is so easy and distinct that there can be no room for doubt about what we are understanding."

  • Intuition means something definite, unlike the common use as a "gut feeling".

  • Example: 2 + 2 = 4 is intuitively true; denying it would require giving up core beliefs about numbers and equality.

  • Other examples include "a three-legged stool has three legs" and "the tallest building is taller than any other building."

  • Some truths rely on definitions, while others rely on mental operations or commonly accepted knowledge.

  • In morality, the proposition that "it is better to be good than to be bad" seems intuitively true.

  • Caution is needed when intuitions extend into areas without consensus.

  • Distinguishing between certain intuitions and mere feelings is crucial.

Common Sense
  • Common sense refers to a basic set of facts or common knowledge.

  • Philosophically, it involves specific claims based on direct sense perception.

  • Philosophers of common sense argue against skepticism of basic sense perception claims.

  • Example: G.E. Moore's proof of the external world by gesturing to his hand and stating, "Here is one hand."

  • Knowledge of one's own hands doesn't need further proof.

  • Common sense can be questioned, but the common-sense philosopher may deem such interrogation unnecessary or excessive.

Experimental Philosophy
  • Experimental philosophy uses empirical methods similar to psychology or cognitive science.

  • It tests philosophical terms and concepts in a laboratory setting.

  • Example: Testing whether people believe free will is necessary for moral responsibility by posing scenarios to research subjects.

  • It aims to confirm that philosophical common sense or intuition aligns with general public opinion.

  • Studies require replication and should align with psychological or biological theories.

  • Experimental philosophers behave more like scientists and adhere to rigorous standards.

Results from Other Disciplines
  • Philosophical claims should consider findings from scientific disciplines.

  • Claims about the natural world should align with natural sciences.

  • Claims about human nature should align with biology and social sciences.

  • Philosophers should welcome evidence from other disciplines to better understand the whole truth.

Summary of Philosophical Evidence Types
  • History: Insights from past philosophers.

  • Intuition: Insight into the nature of things.

  • Common Sense: Claims based on direct sense perception.

  • Experimental Philosophy: Testing concepts in a lab.

  • Results from Other Disciplines: Evidence from scientific fields.

Logic

  • Logic is the science of reasoning.

  • It formalizes the process of providing reasons for claims.

  • Logic helps assess whether claims are well-founded and consistent.

  • Claims are the product of arguments.

  • An argument is a series of sentences where premises provide evidence for a conclusion.

  • Arguments can be reconstructed to identify premises and conclusions.

  • Formal techniques evaluate whether claims are well-supported.

  • Poorly supported claims may be true, but supporting them is irrational.

  • Arguments can explain phenomena by reasoning backward from observations to evidence.

  • Logical reconstruction provides rational explanations for observations.

Coherence
  • Logic assesses the consistency of a set of claims or beliefs.

  • Beliefs should be internally consistent.

  • Coherence: Statements/beliefs can be true simultaneously.

  • Contradictory statements/beliefs cannot be true simultaneously.

  • Inconsistent beliefs indicate at least one false claim.

  • Philosophers must revise beliefs or give up some to maintain consistency.

  • Logical consistency does not guarantee truth, but inconsistency indicates falsehood.

Conceptual Analysis

  • Conceptual analysis clarifies and understands philosophical statements.

  • It involves breaking apart complex ideas into simpler ones.

  • It aims for clearer and more workable definitions of concepts.

  • Dictionary definitions describe ordinary usage but may not be coherent, accurate, or precise.

  • Philosophers determine the meaning of terms and whether it fits within a larger understanding of the world.

  • Sentences in natural language can be translated into a formal, symbolic language.

  • Sentences can be broken into names/object identifiers and concepts/predicates.

  • The role of conceptual analysis is to identify the right predicates and clarify the relationship between them.

  • For any sentence, ask: What is being predicated? How is it being predicated?

Descriptions
  • Objects can be analyzed using descriptions.

  • Bertrand Russell identified definite descriptions to analyze proper names or objects.

  • Subject terms can be substituted with descriptive sentences that uniquely identify them.

  • Proper names are definite descriptions in disguise.

  • Definite descriptions clarify what we are talking about without gestures, context, or direct experience.

  • Understanding definite descriptions and predicates reduces ambiguity and vagueness.

Enumeration
  • Enumerating component parts helps understand a concept.

  • Example: A governmental body consists of its legislature, executive, and judicial branches.

  • Claims about the whole can be analyzed as claims about its parts.

  • Enumeration can be used to understand abstract concepts.

  • Example: Aristotle says wisdom is composed of scientific knowledge plus understanding.

Thought Experiments
  • Thought experiments are hypothetical scenarios that clarify the relationship between concepts.

  • They isolate features of a concept and place it in relationship with other concepts.

  • Philosophers have used them for a long time.

  • Example: Plato's ideal city in The Republic to identify the source of justice.

  • Example: Aristotle's claim that nature abhors a vacuum by imagining a void.

  • Thought experiments test moral theories by applying them to hypothetical cases.

  • They can support or undermine moral theories.

Summary of Conceptual Analysis Methods
  • Predicates: Descriptive terms used to clarify statements.

  • Descriptions: Definite descriptions analyze names and object terms.

  • Enumeration: Identifying the component parts of a concept.

  • Thought Experiments: Hypothetical scenarios that test and compare concepts.

Tradeoffs

  • Philosophers aim to understand how things connect broadly.

  • No single philosophical picture is obviously compelling.

  • There will be competing pictures, each with strong reasons.

  • We must evaluate each picture and understand the tradeoffs they impose.

  • Consider the practical and logical implications of beliefs.

Biting the Bullet
  • "Biting the bullet" means accepting negative consequences of a view because it is attractive for other reasons.

  • Example: A philosopher committed to determinism might accept that free will is an illusion.

  • Example: A philosopher focused on total quantity of effects of an action might accept harming an individual.

  • Be honest about the logical and moral consequences of views.

Reflective Equilibrium
  • Reflective equilibrium assesses the logical and moral consequences of our thinking.

  • It uses judgments about particular cases to revise principles, rules, or theories about general cases.

  • Theoretical and practical beliefs must cohere utilizing this method.

  • It involves revising theoretical stances based on practical judgments.

  • Reflective equilibrium justifies beliefs by assessing their logical consistency, incorporating practical judgments.

  • Students should be aware of both theoretical commitments and practical concerns.

https://openstax.org/books/introduction-philosophy/pages/1-2-how-do-philosophers-arrive-at-truth