The Rationality Principle

Explanation in Social Sciences
  • Social explanations resemble physical explanations but have unique challenges.

  • Two types of problems:

    • Singular events: Explaining one-off events (e.g., a specific lunar eclipse).

    • Type of event: Explaining recurring events (e.g., seasonal unemployment).

  • Social sciences use models to create typical scenarios.

Models in Natural and Social Sciences
  • Natural sciences: Explain events like lunar eclipses with models (sun, earth, moon).

    • Models should show eclipses happening with a full moon.

    • Leads to deeper questions, like Newton's laws of motion.

    • Initial conditions are included in the model.

    • Universal laws (like Newton's) drive the model.

  • Social sciences: Use situational analysis to model social situations.

    • Helps in understanding social events.

Animating Social Models
  • Avoid using human psychology to drive social models.

  • Situational analysis uses aims and knowledge, not concrete experiences.

  • Assume agents act appropriately based on the situation and 'Rationality principle'.

    • Situation includes goals and knowledge.

    • 'Rationality principle': acting appropriately to the situation.

The Rationality Principle
  • The rationality principle suggests people act rationally.

  • It's used to integrate explanatory theory into the situation analysis.

  • The animating law becomes a zero principle.

    • Actors act within the confines of the model.

Rationality Principle as Methodological Postulate
  • The rationality principle is not a testable theory.

  • Situational analyses are the actual testable theories.

  • Models can be assessed and debated.

  • Testing models isn't straightforward.

    • Models are simplified.

    • Simplification reduces testability.

    • Tests can identify the best models.

    • Historical research can test situational analysis.

Validity of the Rationality Principle
  • The rationality principle is often seen as inherently valid but is actually false.

  • People don't always act appropriately.

  • There are vast differences in how people see situations.

  • A principle that isn't universally true is false.

  • An explanation using a false principle and a model is also false.

Models as Oversimplifications
  • All models, whether physical or social, are simplifications.

  • The rationality principle is debated.

    • Methodological: Not empirically tested or false.

    • Empirical: Part of social theories and tested/rejected with the theory.

  • The rationality principle is part of every testable social theory.

Testing Theories and the Rationality Principle
  • When a theory fails, identify the problem area.

  • It's better to question the model, not the rationality principle, because models are more informative and testable.

  • The rationality principle is known to be false but is a useful approximation.

  • If a theory fails significantly, the model is likely the cause.

  • Replacing the rationality principle introduces uncertainty.

  • Theories are tested holistically, comparing different theories using the rationality principle.

Churchill's Dictum and the Rationality Principle
  • Churchill: Wars are a competition in incompetence.

  • This model doesn't rely on the rationality principle.

  • Leaders may not fully understand the situation.

  • Actions can be seen as appropriate based on their limited view.

  • To understand actions, reconstruct a broader view of the situation.

  • Actions align with their understanding of the situation.

Understanding Actions
  • The rationality principle helps understand actions, even irrational ones.

  • Explain actions based on their aims and information.

  • Understand actions by considering a wider context.

  • Understanding involves seeing the logic in their (potentially mistaken) view.

  • Explain how they developed that view.

  • They rigidly stick to their view to maintain a sense of understanding.

Freud and Irrationality
  • Freud isn't about discovering irrationality, but uses situational models and the rationality principle.

  • Neurosis is a childhood response to a difficult situation.

  • Choosing a neurosis is rational, like avoiding a car only to be hit by a bike.

  • Freud's therapy is rationalistic: understanding the childhood situation resolves the neurosis.

Rationality vs. Tautology
  • Explaining everything with rationality isn't tautological.

  • Tautologies are obviously true, while the rationality principle is an approximation and is false.

Rationality and Irrationality
  • Healthy beliefs are open to correction.

  • Fixed opinions resemble those of someone who is mad.

  • Committed individuals resist correcting even widely accepted mistakes.

  • Those who value commitment over reason are irrational.

  • This commitment arises from fear of losing their worldview.

  • Commitment and fanaticism are close to irrationality.

Conclusion: Rationality as a Personal Attitude vs. The Rationality Principle
  • Rationality as a personal attitude: willingness to revise beliefs through discussion.

  • The rationality principle doesn't assume people are rational in this way.

  • It's a minimal principle assuming actions fit our view of the situation.

  • The rationality principle drives explanatory models.

  • It's known to be approximate but reduces uncertainty in models.

  • Without it, models would be erratic.