Hedonism and Theories of Well-Being (Lecture Video Notes)
Hedonism and Theories of Well-Being — Class Notes
Structure of class (as per transcript):
- Intro to hedonic theories, then two central arguments for/against hedonism (correlation argument and motivation argument)
- Objection: experience machine
- Basic logic review (claims, premises, conclusions, validity, soundness, and argument reconstruction)
- Practical activity: reconstruct arguments and apply to thought experiments
Administrative and classroom logistics mentioned:
- Attendance: students provided with a small piece of paper for attendance
- Reader responses: optional comments, used to guide focus under numbers 1–3 in the plan
- Late submission policy for reader response: if submitted after deadline, ~50% credit (0.5 out of 1). Can submit within the same week for partial credit, effectively:
- If due last night, you can submit by the end of the week for 12.5 (partial credit reference)
- Feedback: instructor happy to provide comments even for pass/fail submissions; using this as practice to improve summarization and argument reconstruction
- Office hours and email: encouraged for clarification or further questions
Agenda for today (summary):
- First, a brief introduction to theories of well-being (three sections on well-being):
- Basic concept of well-being
- Different options for explaining what is intrinsically good for a person
- Then delve into hedonism and central claims
- Then discuss arguments for and against hedonism as presented in the lecture chapter, with a focus on:
- The correlation argument
- The motivation argument
- The objection based on the experience machine
- Ongoing integration of basic logic throughout the class
Theory of well-being: core questions and terms
- Core question: What is intrinsically good for a person? (prudential/good for a person) rather than broadly moral good
- Welfare subject: a subject capable of having well-being (could be humans, animals, possibly AI depending on whether pain/pleasure can be felt or experienced)
- Why focus on welfare subject? To discuss what goes well or badly for a person (or candidate subject) regardless of relational or moral considerations
- Prudential good (prudential value): equivalently what is physically or practically good for a person; used interchangeably with well-being/welfare; contrasted with moral good
- Distinction: prudential good vs moral good; intrinsic vs instrumental goods
- Role of relationships and goals in well-being: common components of a good life include meaningful interpersonal relationships, personal achievements, hobbies, meaningful projects, contribution to something bigger
- Why discuss prudential good? For individual-level concern (e.g., policy implications, distribution of resources within families or communities)
- Instrumental vs intrinsic goods (illustrative discussion):
- Instrumental goods are means to other goods (e.g., money can enable education, experiences, etc.)
- Intrinsic goods are valuable in themselves (the extent to which something is good for its own sake rather than as a means to something else)
- Example discussion: health as a potential intrinsic good vs instrumental good (some argue health is valuable insofar as it enables pursuing other goods; others argue it can also be intrinsically good depending on theory)
- Evolutionary perspective: possible to connect evolutionary explanations to theories of well-being, e.g., brain-hardwired tendencies toward pleasure/pain avoidance; not decisive for any theory but compatible with reasoning about well-being
- Paradigmatic cases: used to identify components of a good life (relationships, achievement, hobbies, contribution, etc.) and to motivate the hedonic theory as a unifying account (pleasure/pain balance) or to motivate alternative theories (value fulfillment, perfectionism)
- The plan for the next sessions: value fulfillment theory, perfectionism; hedonic theory will be examined first, with attention to two main arguments and the experience machine obstacle
Hedonism: the central claims
- Core claim (three-part bundle):
- Claim 1: All and only pleasure is intrinsically good for a person. ext{IntrinsicGood}( ext{pleasure}) ext{ and only if pleasure is intrinsically good}
- Claim 2: All and only pain (suffering) is intrinsically bad for a person. ext{IntrinsicBad}( ext{pain}) ext{ and only if pain is intrinsically bad}
- Claim 3: The overall good for a person is the balance of pleasure over pain (the hedonic balance); in the long run, one should maximize pleasure and minimize pain. This yields the guiding principle: maximize the net hedonic balance
- Formal flavor: If we denote pleasure by P and pain by Q (pain = negative hedonic value), then the hedonic balance could be represented as B = ext{Pleasure} - ext{Pain} = P - Q and aim to maximize B
- Three conceptions of pleasure within hedonism (types of hedonic theories):
- Attitudinal hedonicism: pleasure is the attitude one has toward something (e.g., pleasure in reading literature even if the activity isn’t always physically pleasant)
- Experiential/feeling-based hedonicism: pleasure is the felt sensation (e.g., enjoying food, entertainment, certain experiences)
- Qualitative hedonicism (Mill): some pleasures are of higher quality than others; not all pleasures are equal in value
- Some philosophers debate the structure of pleasure and pain; all three forms can be reconciled under a hedonic framework; the debate is about how to understand pleasure and pain, not about whether hedonicism holds at the level of claims 1–3
- Epistemic note: even if a person cannot predict perfectly which option will maximize pleasure, a hedonist maintains that the standard is to maximize pleasure and minimize pain in general; epistemic mistakes do not refute the hedonic standard
- Distinction between intrinsic vs instrumental good (revisited):
- Some things may be intrinsically good but we often rely on them as vehicles to other goods (e.g., achieving health to pursue other goals). The hedonic view tends to focus on hedonic value rather than broad moral valuation, though the practical life may involve a mix of goods
- Clarifications about intrinsic vs instrumental goods within hedonism: focus is on what is good for the individual, not necessarily on the moral evaluation of actions; there can be altruistic actions where the motive is pleasure, but the hedonic calculation looks at net pleasure/pain for the agent
- Clarification on the scope of hedonism: initially focusing on prudential (individual) well-being; other modules may address moral and political aspects of well-being
- Practical questions: what counts as pleasure? What about long-term vs short-term pleasure? How to handle cases like health or risky activities? How to address cases where pleasure is achieved at the expense of other values (e.g., moral considerations, long-term consequences)?
Key distinctions and clarifications used in the discussion
- Intrinsic vs instrumental value:
- Intrinsic good: valuable in itself (for its own sake)
- Instrumental good: valuable as a means to something else
- Prudential good vs moral good:
- Prudential good: good for the individual's life (self-focused)
- Moral good: good relative to moral considerations about others
- Welfare subject vs non-welfare subject: who counts as a subject that can have well-being; debates include animals, AI, etc.
The “paradigmatic cases” exercise (introduction to a good life)
- Students imagine a good life for themselves (brief 30 seconds) and share components
- Common themes: meaningful interpersonal relationships, strong community, personal achievement, meaningful hobbies or projects, contribution to something larger
- The goal: to understand why these disparate elements can be seen as contributing to well-being and to motivate the hedonic explanation that these experiences yield pleasure and/or avoid pain
- The plan: compare these intuitions to hedonic theory vs value fulfillment vs perfectionism in later sessions
The “evolutionary” and other theoretical contexts mentioned
- Evolutionary explanations may help explain why certain pleasures/pains are valued (e.g., brain wiring toward pleasure and pain avoidance), but they do not settle the philosophical question of what is intrinsically good
- It is acknowledged that such explanations could be compatible with various theories of well-being
The role of argument structure in the discussion
- Premises and conclusion: arguments have premises that support a conclusion; the form/structure matters for assessing the argument
- Validity: an argument is valid if, assuming all premises are true, the conclusion must be true; the form is what guarantees this logical connection
- Soundness: a valid argument with true premises is sound; otherwise, it is not sound
- An example form discussed: If P then Q; P; therefore Q (Modus Ponens)
- Another form: If P then Q; Not Q; therefore Not P (Modus Tollens)
- Common invalid form: Not P; Therefore Not Q (Denying the antecedent) or other forms that do not preserve the logical connection
- The correlation argument (for hedonism) is treated as a structure to be evaluated for validity and then for soundness (depending on the truth of the premises)
- The discussion notes that even a valid argument can be unsound if premises are false; likewise, a sound argument could be undermined if premises are revised or attacked
The correlation argument (for hedonism) – logical structure and evaluation
- Premise: There is a correlation between high hedonic value and high overall welfare/well-being
- Premise (conjectural): The relation is causal or at least sufficiently explanatory to yield hedonic well-being as ultimately identical to welfare
- Conclusion: Hedonism is true (that all and only pleasure is intrinsically good, and thus welfare is governed by hedonic balance)
- Critical note from the discussion: Correlation does not imply causation; there could be a third variable accounting for both high hedonic value and good life outcomes
- The importance of evaluating premises' truth rather than assuming them
- The idea of soundness requires not only a valid form but true premises; if premises are questionable (e.g., correlation implying causation), soundness fails even if the form is valid
The motivation argument (for hedonism)
- Structure (illustrative): People pursue multiple things (money, knowledge, achievement) but are at least partly motivated by pleasure and the avoidance of pain
- Conclusion: Pleasure is the only thing intrinsically valuable; if something is the sole intrinsic value, it makes life go well when maximized and pain minimized
- The argument can be combined with correlation premises to yield a stronger case; but often premises require careful justification to remain persuasive
- The instructor demonstrates how to modify and combine existing arguments to create new versions, highlighting the need to show that the proposed conclusion follows from the given premises
The experience machine (Nozick) thought experiment – overview
- Original inspiration: Robert Nozick’s thought experiment in his book; modern discussion sometimes adapts it (e.g., “experience machine” variants)
- Basic idea: a machine that can simulate a life yielding maximum pleasure; you could plug in to live a perfectly Hedonistic life while your actual experiences and external world remain unaffected
- The two-character case used in the class: Trudy (lives a real-life, challenging, morally meaningful life in New York) vs Flora (lives a life entirely experienced inside the machine during the same time period)
- The task for students: indicate which life they would prefer and why; private responses are collected to avoid social conformity effects
- The intuitive conclusion in class: most students would prefer Trudy’s life (the real, authentic life with agency, effort, and meaningful relationships) over Flora’s simulated life of pleasure
- Logical form of the objection: This thought experiment is a reductio ad absurdum against the thesis that all and only pleasure is intrinsically good (the premise of hedonic theory). If hedonism were true, Trudy and Flora would have the same level of well-being, but intuitively many think Trudy’s life is better due to authenticity, agency, and meaningful achievements
- The form of the Nozick argument used: a valid conditional argument that, when the premises are assumed to be true, leads to the conclusion that hedonic alternatives can yield absurd or undesirable outcomes (i.e., all-pleasure life is not necessarily the best for well-being)
- Key issues raised in class discussions about the experience machine
- The source of experiences: real causal sources (external world vs internal simulation) matters for some conceptions of well-being
- Exercise of agency: making real choices and performing actions vs passive mental states
- The role of authenticity and achievement in well-being; whether simulated pleasures can count toward genuine well-being
- The possibility that Flora’s life could still involve meaningful decisions within the machine; however, even with simulated agency, many participants feel it lacks the same value as real-life agency
- The ethical and practical implications: if experiences within the machine are as good as real-life experiences, should we always choose simulation? If not, what does this imply about intrinsic values beyond mere pleasure?
Reconstruction and critical thinking in argument analysis
- Strategy 1: Start with a central claim (e.g., all and only pleasure is intrinsically good) and reconstruct a chain of consequences; then identify where the argument might fail (absent premises or invalid steps) by exploring counterfactuals or absurd consequences
- Strategy 2: Start with a robust argument (correlation + motivation) and then generate objections by adding hypothetical scenarios or alternative premises to see if the conclusion still