Definition: Divine command theory posits that actions are morally right or wrong based on whether they are commanded by God.
Example: In the Old Testament, God initially commands Noah and his descendants not to eat meat but later permits it under specific conditions (Genesis 9:3-4).
Key Aspects of Divine Command Theory
Historical Context: This theory is historically significant in discussions of morality under religious belief.
Application Across Religions: The concept is universal; it applies to any deity (e.g., God, Zeus, Allah) with appropriate commands.
Core Idea: Morality is dependent upon God's commands, meaning that without a deity, notions of right and wrong cease to exist.
The Euthyphro Dilemma
Origin: Introduced by Socrates in Plato's dialogue "The Euthyphro."
Key Question: "Do the gods love actions because they are pious, or are actions pious simply because the gods love them?"
Rephrased for Divine Command Theory: "Does God tell us to do right because it is right, or is it right because God says it is?"
Unsatisfactory Alternatives in the Dilemma
Option 1: If right exists independently of God's commands, then divine command theory collapses. This implies a moral standard external to God.
Option 2: If we say that actions are right solely because of God's commands, it raises concerns about God's nature, suggesting He could arbitrarily declare immoral actions as right.
Implications of Option 2: This could imply God might command morally reprehensible acts like torture, challenging the notion of God as a perfect being.
Perfect Being's Rationality: Belief in God's perfection necessitates rationality in His commands, suggesting that right and wrong might exist beyond God's will.
Changing Moral Commandments
Example of Dietary Laws: God's command about meat consumption changes based on circumstances, suggesting that moral standards can evolve.
Rationale for Change: Initial prohibitions may have practical reasons (e.g., health, safety), which can become irrelevant over time.
Implications for Moral Education
Teaching Morality: Can moral teachings be divorced from divine command? Shafer-Landau suggests promoting moral behavior should rely on intrinsic understanding rather than fear of divine punishment.
Teaching without Theology: A moral framework that does not depend on the existence of God is necessary for broader acceptance across differing belief systems.
Moral Independence: Morality does not necessitate a common theological belief, as evidenced by differing interpretations among believers and non-believers.
Common Misunderstandings and Challenges
Biblical Interpretations: Variances in interpreting passages (e.g., “Thou shalt not kill”) reflect how moral instructions are applied differently in society.
Scriptural Conflicts: Different beliefs about morality lead to diverse interpretations within the same religious tradition.
Importance of Dialogue: Engaging in discussions about moral beliefs must be done respectfully to avoid shutting down conversation.
Non-Theological Moral Arguments
Importance of Reason: Moral arguments should explore rational, non-theological bases for morality to foster understanding among individuals with diverse beliefs.
Engagement in Moral Discourse: Non-theological discussions are often more productive when addressing moral disagreements.
Summary and Reflective Questions
Should moral teachings rely heavily on religious texts?
What implications does this debate have for raising children with a moral compass that is independent of specific religious doctrine?
How do personal convictions influence perceptions of others' beliefs in a diverse moral landscape?