Note
0.0(0)
CE

Two Senses of Change

1. Review: Where We Are in Lewis’s Theory

• Earlier lectures established two pillars of David Lewis’s position on time travel:

  • Logical possibility: Travel to the past is not self-contradictory if, and only if, the traveler’s actions are consistent with the history from which they depart.

  • Grandfather-paradox deflation: Apparent paradoxes dissolve once we remember that the traveler’s past actions are already part of a single, internally consistent history.
    • Today’s focus: Whether and how such a traveler can really make a difference once back in the past.

2. The Worry: “Powerless Robots” or “Ghostly Observers”

• Common intuition: If a traveler’s deeds are already located at earlier external times, the traveler seems pre-programmed—a puppet unable to intervene.
• Extreme version: The traveler becomes a mere spectator, condemned to watch but never influence events.
• Lewis rejects both pictures. He insists a traveler can be:

  • Concretely present in the past (a flesh-and-blood agent).

  • Deliberative: holding desires, weighing options, making choices.

  • Causally efficacious—but only in the correct sense of “change.”

3. Two Distinct Senses of “Change”

Lewis introduces a crucial distinction:

3.1 Replacement Change (RC)

• Core idea: One state of affairs is literally swapped out for another.
• Paradigm example:

  • An intact glass falls and shatters → intact glass is gone, replaced by shards.
    • Key features:

  • Applies to concrete objects.

  • Implies an earlier state ceases to exist and is superseded.

  • Suitable metaphor: “Erasing and overwriting” history.

3.2 Counterfactual Change (CFC)

• Core idea: We measure impact by comparing what actually happens with what would have happened had some antecedent condition been absent.
• Formally: A counterfactual conditional p \rightarrow_{cf} q (read: “If p had occurred, q would have occurred”).
• No literal overwriting occurs; history happens once. We simply note that alternative possibilities were open.

4. Why RC Cannot Apply to Times

• Times (past, present, future) are not objects that can be physically replaced.
• Illustration: Last-minute lunch reschedule

  • Plan: meet at 12:00 today.

  • Friend texts to shift to tomorrow.

  • We did not experience two competing futures with and without the lunch, one of which was deleted.
    • Therefore:

  • No replacement change is possible for any temporal location (past or future).

  • RC is strictly a matter of object-level alterations, not timeline rewrites.

5. CFC in Ordinary Life

• Alarm-clock story

  • Fact: Alarm sounded → speaker was on time.

  • Counterfactual: \text{If (alarm fails)} \rightarrow \text{(speaker late)}.

  • The day existed only in its actual version; nevertheless, the alarm mattered.
    • Battle of Waterloo

  • Historical judgment (per Wellington): \text{If (Blücher late)} \rightarrow \text{Napoleon wins}.

  • Blücher’s timely arrival shaped history without erasing a previously victorious France.

6. Application to Time Travel

• Lewis’s claim: A traveler can realize counterfactual change in the past while never effecting replacement change.
• Mechanism: Their causal contributions are built into the single consistent history.
• Outcome: The past is different because they were there; yet there is no second, overwritten past.

7. Illustrative Time-Travel Scenarios

• “Hitler and the Tram”

  • Setup: Traveler appears in Vienna, 1908, flash startles Hitler → Hitler steps back, avoids tram.

  • Counterfactual: \text{If (traveler absent)} \rightarrow \text{Hitler dies}.

  • Effect: Traveler unwittingly ensures Hitler’s survival. History includes this influence once and for all.
    • “Editing the Gettysburg Address”

  • Traveler meets Lincoln, who is torn between two drafts.

  • Advice: Choose the now-famous “conceived in liberty” version.

  • Counterfactual: \text{If (traveler silent)} \rightarrow \text{alternative speech}.

  • Outcome: Traveler shapes the sole existing rendition, yet does not delete an earlier speech from the record.

8. Philosophical Pay-offs and Implications

• Agency preserved: Travelers decide and act; their freedom is compatible with a fixed, consistent timeline.
• No fatalism: Consistency ≠ inevitability. It only forbids actions that never were part of history.
• Ontological economy: No need for branching timelines or multiple histories (at least within Lewis’s single-timeline model).
• Ethical dimension: Travelers bear responsibility for outcomes they help bring about (e.g., unintentionally saving Hitler).

9. Links to Broader Lewisian Themes & Earlier Lectures

• Modal realism & counterfactuals: The same analytical machinery Lewis uses for ordinary “what-ifs” underwrites time-travel talk.
• Grandfather paradox revisited: The paradox arises only if we assume replacement change is possible for times; Lewis shows that assumption is mistaken.
• Practical upshot: Planning a time-travel mission must account for the fact that whatever you will do is already part of the past—but this still includes acts with genuine causal influence in the CFC sense.

Note
0.0(0)