knowt logo

Epistemology

How Do We Experience the World Around Us?

Rationalism and Empiricism

These two foundational theories offer different explanations for how we acquire knowledge:

  • Rationalism: Knowledge is primarily acquired through reason and intellectual intuition. 

    • Key rationalists like René Descartes, Baruch Spinoza, and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz argue that certain knowledge, such as mathematical truths, is innate and can be accessed through deductive reasoning.

  • Empiricism: Knowledge is primarily acquired through sensory experience. 

    • Prominent empiricists like John Locke, George Berkeley, and David Hume argue that the mind starts as a blank slate and that all knowledge is derived from experience through induction and observation.

Kinds of Knowledge

Epistemology

  • Definition and Origin

    • Epistemology: The study or science of knowledge.

    • Greek Roots: "Episteme" (knowledge) and "logos" (study or science).

    • Relation to “-ology”: The root "logos" is also the basis for terms like psychology, anthropology, and logic.

Uses of the Term “Knowledge”

  • Psychological Conviction: Knowing in the sense of strong belief (e.g., "I just knew it wouldn’t rain, but then it did").

  • Philosophical (Factive) Sense: Knowing something that is true. Philosophers argue that one cannot know something that is not the case.

Types of Knowledge

  • Procedural Knowledge (Know-how)

    • Examples: Knowing how to ride a bicycle, knowing how to drive from one city to another.

  • Acquaintance Knowledge (Familiarity)

    • Examples: Knowing a person (e.g., the department chairperson), knowing a place (e.g., Philadelphia).

  • Propositional Knowledge (Knowledge-that)

    • Definition: Knowledge expressed by declarative sentences that describe facts or states of affairs.

    • Examples: "Dogs are mammals," "2+2=4," "It is wrong to murder innocent people for fun."

    • Characteristics: Propositions can be true or false.

Focus of Epistemologists

  • Propositional Knowledge: The primary focus in epistemology, dealing with statements of fact.

  • Declarative Sentences: Statements that describe facts or states of affairs.

Scope of Propositional Knowledge

  • Wide Range of Matters: Includes scientific, geographical, mathematical knowledge, self-knowledge, and any other field.

  • Knowable vs. Unknowable Truths: Epistemology seeks to establish what can or cannot be known.

Meta-Epistemology

  • Study of Criteria for Knowledge: Understanding the fundamental nature of knowledge itself.

Sources of Propositional Knowledge

  • A Priori Knowledge

    • Definition: Knowledge independent of experience, known through reason alone.

    • Examples: Logical truths (e.g., law of non-contradiction), abstract claims (e.g., ethical claims).

  • A Posteriori Knowledge

    • Definition: Knowledge dependent on sensory experience.

    • Examples: Knowing the color or shape of an object, geographical knowledge.

Philosophical Stances

  • Rationalism: Belief that all knowledge is ultimately grounded in reason.

  • Empiricism: Belief that all knowledge is ultimately grounded in experience.

Collective Knowledge

  • Social Epistemology: The study of how groups, institutions, or collective bodies acquire knowledge.

The Nature of Propositional Knowledge

  • Focus: Narrowed to propositional knowledge, which involves statements of fact.

  • Central Questions:

    • What constitutes knowledge?

    • What does it mean for someone to know something?

    • What distinguishes someone who knows something from someone who does not?

Characterizing Knowledge

  • General Characterization Needed: A broad definition applicable to any kind of proposition.

  • Analysis of the Concept of Knowledge:

    • Epistemologists aim to identify a correct and complete analysis of knowledge.

    • This involves identifying necessary and sufficient conditions.

Necessary and Sufficient Conditions

  • Necessary Conditions: Conditions that must be met for a proposition to qualify as knowledge.

  • Sufficient Conditions: Conditions that, if met, ensure that a proposition qualifies as knowledge.

Traditional Analysis of Knowledge

  • The standard definition in epistemology traditionally includes the following conditions:

  • Justified True Belief: The tripartite definition, where knowledge is seen as a belief that is true and justified.

    • Belief: The person must believe the proposition.

    • Truth: The proposition must be true.

    • Justification: The person must have adequate justification for believing the proposition.

Challenges and Refinements

  • Gettier Problems: Cases presented by Edmund Gettier showing that justified true belief may not be sufficient for knowledge, leading to further refinements and additional conditions.

Beliefs

Belief as a Component of Knowledge

Knowledge as a Mental State

  • Knowledge is Mental: Knowledge exists in the mind and cannot be attributed to unthinking things.

  • Specific Kind of Mental State: Knowledge is distinct from other mental states like desires and intentions.

Relationship Between Belief and Knowledge

  • Knowledge as a Kind of Belief: To have knowledge about something, one must have beliefs about it.

  • Example: If someone does not believe they will receive a raise, they cannot know they will receive one.

Occurrent vs. Non-Occurrent Beliefs

  • Occurrent Beliefs: Beliefs that an individual is actively thinking about at a given moment.

  • Non-Occurrent (Background) Beliefs: Beliefs that are held in the background and not actively considered at a specific time.

  • Knowledge Types: Most knowledge is non-occurrent (background knowledge), while a smaller portion is occurrent.

Truth

Truth as a Condition of Knowledge

Belief and Knowledge

  • Belief is Necessary but Not Sufficient: To know something, one must believe it, but belief alone does not constitute knowledge.

  • True vs. False Beliefs: We aim to increase our true beliefs and minimize false ones to acquire knowledge.

Purpose of Beliefs

  • Descriptive Aim: The typical purpose of forming beliefs is to describe or capture the way things actually are, seeking a match between mind and world.

  • Other Purposes: Beliefs may also be formed for reasons such as self-deception or creating positive attitudes, but these do not aim at knowledge.

Objective Truth

  • Assumption of Objective Truth: The concept assumes that there is an objective reality that beliefs can match or fail to match.

  • Factive Knowledge: Knowledge in the factive sense requires that there be facts to know. Without facts, there can be no knowledge.

Truth as a Condition of Knowledge

  • Truth Requirement: For a belief to constitute knowledge, it must be true.

  • Relativism Challenge: Some relativists deny objective truth, which would imply that knowledge, as traditionally understood, cannot exist.

  • Domain-Specific Truth: In domains without objective truths (e.g., subjective beauty), beliefs cannot constitute knowledge.

Justification

Justification as a Component of Knowledge

Necessity of Justification

  • True Belief is Not Sufficient: Knowledge requires not just a true belief but a true belief formed in the right way.

  • Right Way: Beliefs must be formed through sound reasoning and solid evidence, not through luck or misinformation.

Definition of Justification

  • Justified Belief: A belief is justified if it is based on evidence and reasoning.

  • Contrast with Unjustified Belief: Unjustified beliefs may be true but are formed through luck, misinformation, or faulty reasoning.

Fallibilism

  • Human Fallibility: The view that humans can have knowledge even if their beliefs might have turned out to be false.

  • Spectrum of Beliefs: Beliefs lie on a spectrum from necessarily true to true by luck, with justified beliefs falling somewhere in between.

Example of Justification

  • Example: If a weatherman predicts a 90% chance of rain and you believe it will rain based on this prediction, your belief is justified even if there was a chance it could have been false.

  • Defeasible Reasoning: Justified beliefs are based on evidence and reasoning that make them likely to be true, even if not absolutely certain.

Independence of Truth and Justification

  • Independent Conditions:

    • Unjustified True Beliefs: Beliefs can be true but unjustified.

    • Justified False Beliefs: Beliefs can be justified but false.

  • Correlation: Justified beliefs are more likely to be true than unjustified ones, but justification alone does not guarantee truth.

The Gettier Problem

Background

  • Justified True Belief (JTB): For a long time, knowledge was thought to be accurately described by the JTB account, which holds that knowledge is a justified true belief.

  • Gettier's Challenge: In 1963, Edmund Gettier published an article presenting cases where justified true belief does not seem to equate to knowledge.

Gettier Cases

  • Structure of Examples: Gettier provided examples where an individual has a belief that is true and justified, yet does not constitute knowledge due to the role of luck.

  • Example of a Stopped Clock:

    • Scenario: A reliable clock stops at 11:56 PM. Twelve hours later, someone glances at it and forms the belief that it is 11:56 AM.

    • True Belief: The belief is true since it coincidentally matches the correct time.

    • Justified Belief: The person has no reason to doubt the clock and is justified in relying on it.

    • Lack of Knowledge: Despite the true and justified belief, the person does not actually know the time due to the role of luck. If they had looked at the clock a bit earlier or later, their belief would have been false.

Implications of Gettier Cases

  • Challenge to JTB: These examples demonstrate that justified true belief can fail to constitute knowledge because of the element of luck.

  • Luck and Justification: The justification condition was meant to ensure knowledge is based on solid evidence, but Gettier cases show that even justified true beliefs can involve luck.

  • Need for Refinement: To address the Gettier Problem, epistemologists must:

    • Re-examine JTB: Determine whether all instances of justified true belief truly constitute knowledge.

    • Refine the Analysis: Propose additional conditions or modifications to the JTB account to exclude cases where luck plays a role.

The No-False-Belief Condition

Initial Proposal

  • Simple Solution: One might think the Gettier Problem can be solved by adding a condition that no false beliefs are involved in the justification process.

  • Revised Analysis: To constitute knowledge, a belief must be:

    • True

    • Justified

    • Formed without relying on any false beliefs

Example and Limitation

  • Original Example: Belief that the clock is working properly (a false belief) justifies the true belief about the time.

  • Modification of Example: Even if no false beliefs are involved, issues remain:

    • True General Belief: Suppose I believe generally that the clock usually works properly (which is true).

    • Justification: This general belief justifies my specific belief that the time is 11:56.

    • Lack of Knowledge: Despite no false beliefs, it still seems I do not know the time because my belief is still based on luck.

Implications

  • Insufficiency of No-False-Belief Condition: Even when all beliefs involved are true, justified true belief can still fail to constitute knowledge if luck plays a role.

  • Persistent Role of Luck: The role of luck in the belief formation process undermines the sufficiency of the no-false-belief condition for defining knowledge.

The No-Defeaters Condition

Concept of Defeaters

  • A defeater is a proposition that, if known or believed, would undermine or invalidate the justification for a belief.

  • Types of Defeaters:

    • Explicit Defeater: A belief or knowledge of a false proposition that would directly contradict the justification.

    • Implicit Defeater: A proposition that is implicitly assumed in the reasoning process and, if false, undermines the justification.

Example of a Defeater

  • Clock Example:

    • False Belief: The belief that the clock is currently working properly is false.

    • Implicit in Reasoning: Even if not explicitly formed, the belief that the clock is working properly is implicit in my reasoning when I look at the clock and believe it is 11:56.

    • Impact of Realization: If I realized the clock wasn’t working, I wouldn’t trust the clock to tell the correct time, and thus my belief about the time would not be justified.

No-Defeaters Condition

  • Condition Explained: To constitute knowledge, a belief must:

    • Be true.

    • Be justified.

    • Have no defeaters—there must not be any false propositions, that if known or believed, would undermine the justification for the belief.

Addressing the Gettier Problem

  • Solving the Issue: By adding the no-defeaters condition, we ensure that the justification for a belief is robust and not based on any false premises or assumptions that could invalidate it.

  • Importance of Truth in Justification: This condition acknowledges that for justification to lead to knowledge, it must not be undermined by any unknown false beliefs.

Acceptance by Epistemologists

  • Support for the Condition: Many epistemologists find this analysis to be correct and sufficient to address cases like those presented by Gettier.

  • Refinement of Knowledge Definition: The addition of the no-defeaters condition refines the traditional JTB (justified true belief) account to handle cases involving luck and false assumptions.

Casual Accounts of Knowledge

  • Causal accounts of knowledge emerge as an alternative to the traditional Justified True Belief (JTB) account in response to the Gettier problem, which reveals that the JTB criteria can be met without constituting true knowledge due to the involvement of luck. 

  • Gettier-type examples demonstrate situations where a belief is justified and true but the connection between the truth and justification involves an element of luck.

Connection Between Truth and Justification:

  • Traditional JTB requires a belief to be justified and true, but Gettier examples show that this is not sufficient for knowledge because the justification and truth can be coincidentally aligned due to luck.

  • In true knowledge cases, the same factors should be responsible for both the justification and the truth of the belief. For instance, a working clock justifies the belief about the time and simultaneously ensures its truth.

Role of Causality:

  • Causal accounts propose that for a belief to be considered knowledge, there must be a direct causal link between the fact that makes the belief true and the person’s belief in that proposition.

  • This approach preserves the truth condition, as the proposition must reflect a fact for a causal relationship to exist.

Incompatibility with Fallibilism:

  • Fallibilism is the notion that a belief can be justified yet false.

    • Causal accounts, however, imply that if there is a causal connection, the belief cannot be false, thus opposing the idea of fallibilism.

  • Causal accounts do not inherently address justification.

    • However, one might attempt to reformulate fallibilism in new terms to reconcile it with causal accounts, though this would require significant modification.

Implications of Causal Accounts:

  • Gettier Problems:

    • Causal accounts aim to eliminate the luck element seen in Gettier cases by ensuring a direct causal link between the fact and the belief, thus resolving the misalignment between truth and justification.

  • Knowledge Definition:

    • Shifts from needing a separate justification condition to focusing on the causal relationship, simplifying the criteria for knowledge but also complicating its practical assessment.

Example:

  • Consider the scenario where you look at a properly functioning clock to determine the time:

  • JTB View: You believe the time is 11:56 because the clock says so (justified), and it is indeed 11:56 (true).

  • Gettier Example: If the clock stopped exactly 24 hours ago at 11:56, your belief is justified (based on the clock) and true (by coincidence) but not knowledge due to the luck element.

  • Causal Account: Your belief that the time is 11:56 is knowledge only if there is a direct causal link between the actual time (fact) and your belief (looking at the working clock), eliminating the coincidental nature.

Nature of Justification

  • The concept of justification is central to the Gettier problem and the analysis of knowledge, yet it remains elusive.

  • To better understand justification, we need to consider how it contributes to the goal of forming true beliefs while avoiding error.

  • This goal implies that justified beliefs are those formed in a way that optimally pursues truth.

  • When we evaluate whether a belief is justified, we essentially assess whether the belief matches the world and whether this match was achieved correctly.

Two Approaches to Justification:

Internalist Approach (Believer's Mind):

  • This perspective focuses on the mental states and processes of the believer.

  • Justification is about the cognitive processes, evidence, and reasons available to the believer.

  • The belief is justified if it is supported by adequate reasons or evidence from the believer's perspective.

  • Emphasizes access to and awareness of justifying factors, suggesting that a belief is justified if the believer can internally verify its truth.

Externalist Approach (The World):

  • This perspective emphasizes the relationship between the belief and the external world.

  • Justification depends on factors outside the believer’s mental states, such as the reliability of the belief-forming process.

  • A belief is justified if it is produced by a process that reliably leads to truth, regardless of the believer's awareness of this reliability.

  • Focuses on the objective connection between the belief and the actual state of affairs in the world.

Implications and Challenges:

Internalism:

  • Provides a clear criterion for the believer to assess justification.

  • Faces challenges in explaining how internal access to reasons or evidence guarantees truth.

  • May struggle with the problem of infinite regress, where justifying beliefs require further justifications.

Externalism:

  • Avoids the regress problem by grounding justification in reliable processes.

  • Can account for justified beliefs even when the believer is unaware of the reliability.

  • May be criticized for disconnecting justification from the believer's perspective and subjective experience.

The Gettier Problem and Justification:

  • Gettier cases illustrate situations where a belief is true and justified yet fails to constitute knowledge due to luck.

  • These cases highlight a gap in the traditional understanding of justification.

  • By exploring internalist and externalist approaches, we aim to refine our understanding of justification to address this gap.

Internalism

  • Core Idea: Justification of a belief is determined solely by factors internal to the believer’s mind.

  • Mental States: Beliefs, sensory inputs (sense data), and beliefs about the relations between various beliefs.

Belief Formation:

  • Mental Process: Beliefs are formed through mental processes involving other mental states.

  • Justification Criteria: For a belief to be justified, it must be supported by other justified mental states.

Basing or Support Relation:

  • Entailment vs. Probability:

    • Entailment: If belief A is based on belief B, the truth of B must entail the truth of A.

    • Probabilistic Support: To allow for fallibility, B must provide good reasons to believe that A is true, making it likely or probable.

Good Reason for Belief:

  • Essential Part of Internalism: A good reason is necessary to establish the justification of a belief.

  • Justified Supporting Beliefs: Belief B must itself be justified to confer justification on belief A.

Regress Problem:

  • Issue of Infinite Justification:

    • Chain of Justification: If belief B must be justified by another belief C, and C by D, this leads to a potential infinite regress.

  • Four Possibilities:

    • Infinite Regress: The series of justified beliefs continues infinitely.

    • Circular Justification: The series of justified beliefs circles back to its beginning (e.g., A is based on B, B on C, C on D, and D on A).

    • Unjustified Starting Point: The series of justified beliefs begins with an unjustified belief.

    • Foundational Belief: The series begins with a belief that is justified, but not by virtue of being based on another justified belief.

Implications for Internalism:

  • Deciding Among Alternatives: An internalist account must choose among these possibilities to provide a coherent theory of justification.

Foundationalism

Regress Argument Analysis:

  • Rejecting Alternatives:

    • Infinite Regress: Unacceptable because the human mind has a finite number of beliefs, and belief formation must start somewhere.

    • Circular Justification: Fallacious because it involves reasoning in a circle.

    • Unjustified Starting Point: Invalid because it makes all subsequent beliefs unjustified.

Conclusion:

  • Alternative 4 is correct by elimination: Some beliefs (basic beliefs) must be justified independently of other beliefs.

Types of Justified Beliefs:

  • Basic Beliefs:

    • Definition: Beliefs that initiate a chain of justification and do not derive their justification from other beliefs.

    • Role: Confer justification on other, non-basic beliefs.

    • Justification Source: Must be justified in a way other than by relations to other beliefs (self-justified or from a non-doxastic source).

  • Non-Basic Beliefs:

    • Definition: Beliefs that derive their justification from other beliefs.

    • Role: Dependent on basic beliefs for their justification.

Asymmetrical Relationship:

  • Structure of Justification:

    • Asymmetry: If belief A is based on belief B, B cannot be based on A.

    • Foundational Structure: Basic beliefs serve as the foundation for non-basic beliefs, creating a non-circular and non-infinite structure of justified beliefs.

Source of Justification for Basic Beliefs:

  • Self-Justified Beliefs: Beliefs that justify themselves inherently without reliance on other beliefs.

  • Non-Doxastic Sources: Sensory inputs or other external factors that provide justification without being beliefs themselves.

Coherentism

Critique of Foundationalism:

  • Dissatisfaction with Foundationalism: Internalists might reject the idea that some beliefs can be justified without being based on other beliefs.

  • Flaw in the Regress Problem: The problem assumes that justification is linear, with beliefs supporting other beliefs in a hierarchical, asymmetrical manner.

Coherentist Approach:

  • Holistic Justification:

    • Mutual Support: Beliefs derive their justification from being part of a coherent set of beliefs that support each other.

    • Non-Linear: Justification is not a linear chain but a network where each belief is justified by its relationship with the entire system of beliefs.

  • Coherence Criteria:

    • Beyond Consistency: Coherence must involve more than logical consistency; there must be a positive support relationship among beliefs.

    • Explanatory Relationship: The beliefs in a coherent set should support each other in a way that they explain or reinforce one another.

Isolation Objection:

  • Potential Problem:

    • Isolated Coherence: A set of beliefs can be coherent yet disconnected from reality.

    • For example, a fictional narrative can be internally coherent but not justified as knowledge about the real world.

Implications for Internalism:

  • Reality Connection: Justification requires not just internal coherence but also a match between beliefs and the actual world.

  • Challenge for Coherentism: To address the isolation objection, coherentists must find a way to ensure that a coherent set of beliefs is also connected to reality.

Externalism

  • Externalism: Justification depends on factors external to the believer’s mind. This approach addresses the isolation objection by ensuring that beliefs are connected to reality.

Reliabilism: The Prominent Version of Externalism

  • Belief Formation Sources:

    • Sources of Beliefs: Sense experience, reason, testimony, memory, etc.

    • Cognitive Processes: The specific processes (e.g., vision, expert testimony) that lead to the formation of beliefs.

Reliability Criterion:

  • Core Principle: A belief is justified if it results from a cognitive process that reliably produces true beliefs.

  • Examples:

    • Vision: Reliable for a normally-sighted person observing a well-lit object.

    • Testimony: Reliable when coming from an expert, unreliable when from a compulsive liar.

The Generality Problem

  • Challenge in Specification:

    • Describing Processes: Cognitive processes can be described at various levels of generality (e.g., vision by a normally-sighted person vs. vision by a normally-sighted person in daylight while looking at an elm tree).

    • Impact on Reliability: Some descriptions might specify a reliable process, while others might not, affecting the justification status of the belief.

Implication:

  • Need for Precision: To determine whether a belief is justified, one must specify the appropriate level of generality for the cognitive process.

The Truetemp Problem (Keith Lehrer)

  • Scenario:

    • Mr. Truetemp: A person with a tempucomp device implanted in his brain that accurately reads the temperature and causes spontaneous true beliefs about it.

    • Unawareness: Truetemp is unaware of the device and its function.

Lehrer's Argument:

  • Ignorance Issue: Truetemp’s ignorance about the source of his true beliefs renders those beliefs unjustified.

  • Awareness Requirement: Lehrer concludes that a belief-forming process must not only be reliable but also that the believer must be aware of the reliability of the process for the beliefs to be justified.

The Extent of Human Knowledge

Sources of Knowledge

  • Empirical Knowledge:

    • Perception and Senses: Empirical facts about the physical world are known through the senses (sight, hearing, smell, touch, taste).

    • Scientific Method: Science exemplifies empirical knowledge through data collection and experiments.

    • Everyday Perception: Most mundane knowledge about our environment is acquired through our sensory experiences.

Reasoning and Inference:

  • Data Analysis: Scientists must analyze collected data to derive knowledge.

  • Inferences: We draw inferences from sensory information to form knowledge.

  • Abstract/Non-Empirical Knowledge: Knowledge of abstract or a priori facts relies on reasoning rather than sensory experience.

Intuition:

  • Direct Access: Intuition is believed to provide direct access to a priori knowledge without needing empirical evidence.

Sustaining and Transmitting Knowledge

  • Memory:

    • Retaining Knowledge: Memory enables us to retain knowledge over time.

    • Past Justification: We can remember something known in the past even if we forget the original justification for that knowledge.

  • Testimony:

    • Knowledge Transmission: Knowledge can be passed from one person to another through testimony.

    • Trusted Sources: Belief in the truth of a proposition can be justified by the testimony of a trusted source.

Skepticism

  • Core Idea: Skepticism is the view that we do not, or cannot, have knowledge, or that we know much less than we think we do.

Types of Skepticism:

  • Local Skepticism:

    • Domain-Specific Doubts: Skepticism concerning specific areas such as mathematics, morality, or the external world.

    • Common Example: Skepticism about the external world is the most well-known form.

  • Global Skepticism:

    • Universal Doubt: The belief that we cannot know anything at all.

Focus of Skepticism:

  • Truth vs. Justification:

    • Truth Skepticism: The view that none of our beliefs are true.

    • Justification Skepticism: The view that none of our beliefs are justified (more common than truth skepticism).

Arguments for Skepticism

  • General Strategy:

    • Challenging Knowledge Claims: Skeptics often question how we know what we claim to know.

    • Need for Argument: Simply questioning knowledge isn't enough; skepticism must be supported by robust arguments.

Prominent Arguments for External World Skepticism

  • Argument from Illusion:

    • Premise: Our senses can deceive us, as evidenced by illusions and hallucinations.

    • Conclusion: If our senses are not always reliable, then we cannot trust them to provide knowledge about the external world.

  • Brain in a Vat Argument:

    • Premise: It's possible that we are brains in vats, experiencing a simulated reality created by some external source.

    • Conclusion: If we cannot rule out this possibility, then we cannot be sure that our sensory experiences correspond to an external reality.

Cartesian Skepticism

  • Skepticism: Descartes explores the possibility that all our beliefs might be unjustified due to systematic deception.

Key Points of Descartes' Argument

  • Inaccuracy of Perceptions:

    • Sensory Deception: Our senses sometimes deceive us (e.g., optical illusions).

    • Dreams vs. Reality: We occasionally mistake dreams for waking experiences, making it difficult to distinguish between them.

  • Evil Demon Hypothesis:

    • Possibility of Deception: It's conceivable that an evil demon is deceiving us, making all our experiences false.

    • Modern Version: The "brain-in-a-vat" scenario, where a brain connected to a computer in a vat receives simulated experiences, illustrates this deception.

Implications of the Argument

  • Unjustified Beliefs:

    • False Beliefs: If some perceptions are false, then some of our beliefs based on these perceptions are also false.

    • Need for Distinction: To be justified in our beliefs, we need a reliable method to distinguish between true and false beliefs.

  • Indistinguishability Problem:

    • Waking vs. Dreaming: No definitive signs distinguish waking life from dreams.

    • Trustworthy vs. Untrustworthy Beliefs: Similarly, no signs distinguish accurate beliefs from those caused by an evil demon or brain-in-a-vat scenario.

Conclusion of the Argument

  • All Beliefs Unjustified: Since we cannot reliably distinguish between true and false beliefs, all our beliefs are potentially unjustified.

  • Skepticism: This leads to a skeptical conclusion that we cannot know anything with certainty.

Descartes' Response to Skepticism in Later Meditations

  • Method of Doubt:

    • Descartes uses hyperbolic doubt to question all beliefs, aiming to find something indubitable.

  • Cogito Ergo Sum ("I think, therefore I am"):

    • Indubitable Belief: Descartes finds that while he can doubt everything, he cannot doubt that he is thinking and therefore exists as a thinking being.

    • Foundation for Knowledge: This becomes the foundational belief upon which he rebuilds his system of knowledge.

  • Existence of God:

    • Proof of a Benevolent God: Descartes argues for the existence of a benevolent God who would not deceive him.

    • Reliability of Clear and Distinct Perceptions: If a benevolent God exists, then clear and distinct perceptions can be trusted as true.

  • Distinguishing Truth from Falsehood:

    • Clear and Distinct Criterion: Descartes proposes that beliefs derived from clear and distinct perceptions are true.

    • Overcoming Skepticism: This provides a way to distinguish between true and false beliefs, countering the skeptical argument.

Humean Skepticism

  • Core Idea:

    • Limitations of Perception: Our senses only provide information about how things appear at a given moment, not about how things actually are or about the unobserved parts of the universe.

    • Role of Reason: Reason is needed to extend our knowledge beyond immediate sensory experiences.

Hume's Critique of Reason

  • Problem of Induction:

    • Inductive Reasoning: We often use past experiences to make generalizations about the future (e.g., the sun has risen every day, so it will rise tomorrow).

    • Hume's Critique: Hume argues that inductive reasoning lacks rational justification.

      • Just because something has happened in the past does not guarantee it will happen in the future.

      • There is no logical necessity connecting past and future events.

  • Causal Inference:

    • Causation: We believe that one event causes another based on our experiences (e.g., striking a match causes it to light).

    • Hume's Critique: Hume contends that our belief in causation is not grounded in reason but in habit or custom.

      • We observe sequences of events and infer a causal connection, but this inference is not rationally justified.

      • We never perceive causation directly; we only see one event following another.

Key Points of Hume's Argument

  • Perception Limits:

    • Immediate Sensory Data: Our senses only provide immediate and limited information about our current environment.

    • Beyond Immediate Perception: Knowledge about anything beyond what we currently perceive cannot be solely derived from the senses.

  • Role of Habit and Custom:

    • Inductive Habit: Our expectation that the future will resemble the past is based on habit, not rational justification.

    • Customary Beliefs: Our beliefs about causation and the unobserved world are customary, formed through repeated associations rather than through reason.

  • Skeptical Conclusion:

    • Unjustified Beliefs: Since reason cannot justify inductive reasoning or causal inferences, our beliefs about the external world beyond immediate perception are unjustified.

    • Persistent Skepticism: Even if we trust our senses, we face skepticism regarding any knowledge claims extending beyond our immediate sensory experiences.

Language and Meaning

  • Language is essential for expressing and communicating knowledge.

  • Philosophical inquiry into language explores how meaning is constructed and understood.

  • Meaning: The significance or interpretation of words and sentences. Theories of meaning include:

    • Referential Theory: Words refer to objects or concepts in the world.

    • Use Theory: Meaning is derived from how words are used in practice (Ludwig Wittgenstein).

    • Truth-Conditional Semantics: The meaning of a sentence is given by the conditions under which it is true.

Truth, Coherence, Correspondence, and Pragmatism

  • These theories offer different criteria for evaluating the truth of statements:

  • Correspondence Theory: A statement is true if it corresponds to a fact or reality.

  • Coherence Theory: A statement is true if it coheres with a consistent system of interconnected beliefs.

  • Pragmatic Theory: A statement is true if it is useful and works in practical terms.

Grammarian Philosophies: A Classical Indian Approach

  • Classical Indian epistemology provides rich insights into the nature of knowledge and the role of language:

  • Nyaya School: Emphasizes logical analysis, debate, and the four means of acquiring knowledge: perception, inference, comparison, and testimony.

  • Buddhist Epistemology: Focuses on perception and inference, with a critical examination of the self and the nature of reality. Key figures include Dignaga and Dharmakirti.

  • Mimamsa and Vedanta: Explore the role of Vedic texts and direct experience in understanding reality. Mimamsa emphasizes ritual and dharma, while Vedanta focuses on metaphysical questions about Brahman and the self.

Challenges to Knowledge and Confirmation of Knowledge

Realism and Skepticism

  • Realism: The view that an external reality exists independently of our perceptions. Realists argue that we can know the world through our sensory experiences and rational inferences.

  • Skepticism: Doubts the possibility of certain knowledge. Skeptics argue that our senses and reasoning are fallible, and thus, we can never achieve absolute certainty.

Arguments from Illusion and Mysticism

  • Illusion: Perceptual errors that challenge the reliability of sensory knowledge. For example, a stick appears bent when partially submerged in water.

  • Mysticism: Claims knowledge through direct, often ineffable, spiritual or transcendental experiences. Mystical knowledge is seen as beyond ordinary sensory or rational understanding.

Subjectivism and Objectivism

  • Subjectivism: The view that knowledge is influenced by individual perspectives and experiences. Truth and justification are seen as relative to the subject.

  • Objectivism: The view that knowledge and truth exist independently of individual beliefs or perceptions. There are objective standards for justification and truth.

Causal Theory, Idealism, Phenomenalism, Perspectivism

Causal Theory

  • The causal theory of knowledge suggests that beliefs are justified when they are caused by the relevant facts or states of affairs in the right way.

  • For instance, seeing a tree and believing that there is a tree because you see it.

Idealism

  • Idealism posits that reality is fundamentally mental or immaterial.

  • Major proponents like George Berkeley argue that objects only exist as perceptions in our minds, and there is no material substance underlying them.

Phenomenalism

  • Phenomenalism claims that physical objects do not exist independently of our sensory experiences.

  • Instead, objects are logical constructions from sensory experiences.

  • This view is closely associated with philosophers like John Stuart Mill.

Perspectivism

  • Perspectivism, associated with Friedrich Nietzsche, suggests that all knowledge is from a particular perspective and that there are no objective truths.

  • Knowledge and truth are seen as contingent on individual or cultural perspectives.

Theories of Justification

  • Justification is the process or reasons that support our beliefs and distinguish knowledge from mere belief.

  • Various theories include:

  • Foundationalism: Beliefs are justified based on basic, self-evident truths or foundational beliefs that do not require further justification.

  • Coherentism: Beliefs are justified by their coherence with other beliefs in a mutually supportive system. There are no foundational beliefs, but rather a web of interconnected beliefs.

  • Reliabilism: Beliefs are justified if they are produced by reliable cognitive processes or methods that generally lead to true beliefs.

  • Virtue Epistemology: Justification depends on the intellectual virtues of the knower, such as open-mindedness, intellectual courage, and intellectual humility.

Knowledge Around the World

Access to Knowledge

  • Access to knowledge varies widely across the globe, influenced by factors such as socioeconomic status, education systems, cultural norms, and political regimes.

  • The digital divide highlights disparities in access to information and technology.

Knowledge and Technology

  • Technology profoundly impacts how knowledge is created, shared, and accessed.

  • The internet, digital media, and artificial intelligence are transforming the landscape of knowledge, raising issues of information overload, digital literacy, and the ethics of technology use.

Knowledge and Power

  • Knowledge is closely linked to power structures. The control and dissemination of knowledge can reinforce or challenge social inequalities.

  • The concept of "knowledge is power" underscores how those who control knowledge can influence societal norms, policies, and governance.

I

Epistemology

How Do We Experience the World Around Us?

Rationalism and Empiricism

These two foundational theories offer different explanations for how we acquire knowledge:

  • Rationalism: Knowledge is primarily acquired through reason and intellectual intuition. 

    • Key rationalists like René Descartes, Baruch Spinoza, and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz argue that certain knowledge, such as mathematical truths, is innate and can be accessed through deductive reasoning.

  • Empiricism: Knowledge is primarily acquired through sensory experience. 

    • Prominent empiricists like John Locke, George Berkeley, and David Hume argue that the mind starts as a blank slate and that all knowledge is derived from experience through induction and observation.

Kinds of Knowledge

Epistemology

  • Definition and Origin

    • Epistemology: The study or science of knowledge.

    • Greek Roots: "Episteme" (knowledge) and "logos" (study or science).

    • Relation to “-ology”: The root "logos" is also the basis for terms like psychology, anthropology, and logic.

Uses of the Term “Knowledge”

  • Psychological Conviction: Knowing in the sense of strong belief (e.g., "I just knew it wouldn’t rain, but then it did").

  • Philosophical (Factive) Sense: Knowing something that is true. Philosophers argue that one cannot know something that is not the case.

Types of Knowledge

  • Procedural Knowledge (Know-how)

    • Examples: Knowing how to ride a bicycle, knowing how to drive from one city to another.

  • Acquaintance Knowledge (Familiarity)

    • Examples: Knowing a person (e.g., the department chairperson), knowing a place (e.g., Philadelphia).

  • Propositional Knowledge (Knowledge-that)

    • Definition: Knowledge expressed by declarative sentences that describe facts or states of affairs.

    • Examples: "Dogs are mammals," "2+2=4," "It is wrong to murder innocent people for fun."

    • Characteristics: Propositions can be true or false.

Focus of Epistemologists

  • Propositional Knowledge: The primary focus in epistemology, dealing with statements of fact.

  • Declarative Sentences: Statements that describe facts or states of affairs.

Scope of Propositional Knowledge

  • Wide Range of Matters: Includes scientific, geographical, mathematical knowledge, self-knowledge, and any other field.

  • Knowable vs. Unknowable Truths: Epistemology seeks to establish what can or cannot be known.

Meta-Epistemology

  • Study of Criteria for Knowledge: Understanding the fundamental nature of knowledge itself.

Sources of Propositional Knowledge

  • A Priori Knowledge

    • Definition: Knowledge independent of experience, known through reason alone.

    • Examples: Logical truths (e.g., law of non-contradiction), abstract claims (e.g., ethical claims).

  • A Posteriori Knowledge

    • Definition: Knowledge dependent on sensory experience.

    • Examples: Knowing the color or shape of an object, geographical knowledge.

Philosophical Stances

  • Rationalism: Belief that all knowledge is ultimately grounded in reason.

  • Empiricism: Belief that all knowledge is ultimately grounded in experience.

Collective Knowledge

  • Social Epistemology: The study of how groups, institutions, or collective bodies acquire knowledge.

The Nature of Propositional Knowledge

  • Focus: Narrowed to propositional knowledge, which involves statements of fact.

  • Central Questions:

    • What constitutes knowledge?

    • What does it mean for someone to know something?

    • What distinguishes someone who knows something from someone who does not?

Characterizing Knowledge

  • General Characterization Needed: A broad definition applicable to any kind of proposition.

  • Analysis of the Concept of Knowledge:

    • Epistemologists aim to identify a correct and complete analysis of knowledge.

    • This involves identifying necessary and sufficient conditions.

Necessary and Sufficient Conditions

  • Necessary Conditions: Conditions that must be met for a proposition to qualify as knowledge.

  • Sufficient Conditions: Conditions that, if met, ensure that a proposition qualifies as knowledge.

Traditional Analysis of Knowledge

  • The standard definition in epistemology traditionally includes the following conditions:

  • Justified True Belief: The tripartite definition, where knowledge is seen as a belief that is true and justified.

    • Belief: The person must believe the proposition.

    • Truth: The proposition must be true.

    • Justification: The person must have adequate justification for believing the proposition.

Challenges and Refinements

  • Gettier Problems: Cases presented by Edmund Gettier showing that justified true belief may not be sufficient for knowledge, leading to further refinements and additional conditions.

Beliefs

Belief as a Component of Knowledge

Knowledge as a Mental State

  • Knowledge is Mental: Knowledge exists in the mind and cannot be attributed to unthinking things.

  • Specific Kind of Mental State: Knowledge is distinct from other mental states like desires and intentions.

Relationship Between Belief and Knowledge

  • Knowledge as a Kind of Belief: To have knowledge about something, one must have beliefs about it.

  • Example: If someone does not believe they will receive a raise, they cannot know they will receive one.

Occurrent vs. Non-Occurrent Beliefs

  • Occurrent Beliefs: Beliefs that an individual is actively thinking about at a given moment.

  • Non-Occurrent (Background) Beliefs: Beliefs that are held in the background and not actively considered at a specific time.

  • Knowledge Types: Most knowledge is non-occurrent (background knowledge), while a smaller portion is occurrent.

Truth

Truth as a Condition of Knowledge

Belief and Knowledge

  • Belief is Necessary but Not Sufficient: To know something, one must believe it, but belief alone does not constitute knowledge.

  • True vs. False Beliefs: We aim to increase our true beliefs and minimize false ones to acquire knowledge.

Purpose of Beliefs

  • Descriptive Aim: The typical purpose of forming beliefs is to describe or capture the way things actually are, seeking a match between mind and world.

  • Other Purposes: Beliefs may also be formed for reasons such as self-deception or creating positive attitudes, but these do not aim at knowledge.

Objective Truth

  • Assumption of Objective Truth: The concept assumes that there is an objective reality that beliefs can match or fail to match.

  • Factive Knowledge: Knowledge in the factive sense requires that there be facts to know. Without facts, there can be no knowledge.

Truth as a Condition of Knowledge

  • Truth Requirement: For a belief to constitute knowledge, it must be true.

  • Relativism Challenge: Some relativists deny objective truth, which would imply that knowledge, as traditionally understood, cannot exist.

  • Domain-Specific Truth: In domains without objective truths (e.g., subjective beauty), beliefs cannot constitute knowledge.

Justification

Justification as a Component of Knowledge

Necessity of Justification

  • True Belief is Not Sufficient: Knowledge requires not just a true belief but a true belief formed in the right way.

  • Right Way: Beliefs must be formed through sound reasoning and solid evidence, not through luck or misinformation.

Definition of Justification

  • Justified Belief: A belief is justified if it is based on evidence and reasoning.

  • Contrast with Unjustified Belief: Unjustified beliefs may be true but are formed through luck, misinformation, or faulty reasoning.

Fallibilism

  • Human Fallibility: The view that humans can have knowledge even if their beliefs might have turned out to be false.

  • Spectrum of Beliefs: Beliefs lie on a spectrum from necessarily true to true by luck, with justified beliefs falling somewhere in between.

Example of Justification

  • Example: If a weatherman predicts a 90% chance of rain and you believe it will rain based on this prediction, your belief is justified even if there was a chance it could have been false.

  • Defeasible Reasoning: Justified beliefs are based on evidence and reasoning that make them likely to be true, even if not absolutely certain.

Independence of Truth and Justification

  • Independent Conditions:

    • Unjustified True Beliefs: Beliefs can be true but unjustified.

    • Justified False Beliefs: Beliefs can be justified but false.

  • Correlation: Justified beliefs are more likely to be true than unjustified ones, but justification alone does not guarantee truth.

The Gettier Problem

Background

  • Justified True Belief (JTB): For a long time, knowledge was thought to be accurately described by the JTB account, which holds that knowledge is a justified true belief.

  • Gettier's Challenge: In 1963, Edmund Gettier published an article presenting cases where justified true belief does not seem to equate to knowledge.

Gettier Cases

  • Structure of Examples: Gettier provided examples where an individual has a belief that is true and justified, yet does not constitute knowledge due to the role of luck.

  • Example of a Stopped Clock:

    • Scenario: A reliable clock stops at 11:56 PM. Twelve hours later, someone glances at it and forms the belief that it is 11:56 AM.

    • True Belief: The belief is true since it coincidentally matches the correct time.

    • Justified Belief: The person has no reason to doubt the clock and is justified in relying on it.

    • Lack of Knowledge: Despite the true and justified belief, the person does not actually know the time due to the role of luck. If they had looked at the clock a bit earlier or later, their belief would have been false.

Implications of Gettier Cases

  • Challenge to JTB: These examples demonstrate that justified true belief can fail to constitute knowledge because of the element of luck.

  • Luck and Justification: The justification condition was meant to ensure knowledge is based on solid evidence, but Gettier cases show that even justified true beliefs can involve luck.

  • Need for Refinement: To address the Gettier Problem, epistemologists must:

    • Re-examine JTB: Determine whether all instances of justified true belief truly constitute knowledge.

    • Refine the Analysis: Propose additional conditions or modifications to the JTB account to exclude cases where luck plays a role.

The No-False-Belief Condition

Initial Proposal

  • Simple Solution: One might think the Gettier Problem can be solved by adding a condition that no false beliefs are involved in the justification process.

  • Revised Analysis: To constitute knowledge, a belief must be:

    • True

    • Justified

    • Formed without relying on any false beliefs

Example and Limitation

  • Original Example: Belief that the clock is working properly (a false belief) justifies the true belief about the time.

  • Modification of Example: Even if no false beliefs are involved, issues remain:

    • True General Belief: Suppose I believe generally that the clock usually works properly (which is true).

    • Justification: This general belief justifies my specific belief that the time is 11:56.

    • Lack of Knowledge: Despite no false beliefs, it still seems I do not know the time because my belief is still based on luck.

Implications

  • Insufficiency of No-False-Belief Condition: Even when all beliefs involved are true, justified true belief can still fail to constitute knowledge if luck plays a role.

  • Persistent Role of Luck: The role of luck in the belief formation process undermines the sufficiency of the no-false-belief condition for defining knowledge.

The No-Defeaters Condition

Concept of Defeaters

  • A defeater is a proposition that, if known or believed, would undermine or invalidate the justification for a belief.

  • Types of Defeaters:

    • Explicit Defeater: A belief or knowledge of a false proposition that would directly contradict the justification.

    • Implicit Defeater: A proposition that is implicitly assumed in the reasoning process and, if false, undermines the justification.

Example of a Defeater

  • Clock Example:

    • False Belief: The belief that the clock is currently working properly is false.

    • Implicit in Reasoning: Even if not explicitly formed, the belief that the clock is working properly is implicit in my reasoning when I look at the clock and believe it is 11:56.

    • Impact of Realization: If I realized the clock wasn’t working, I wouldn’t trust the clock to tell the correct time, and thus my belief about the time would not be justified.

No-Defeaters Condition

  • Condition Explained: To constitute knowledge, a belief must:

    • Be true.

    • Be justified.

    • Have no defeaters—there must not be any false propositions, that if known or believed, would undermine the justification for the belief.

Addressing the Gettier Problem

  • Solving the Issue: By adding the no-defeaters condition, we ensure that the justification for a belief is robust and not based on any false premises or assumptions that could invalidate it.

  • Importance of Truth in Justification: This condition acknowledges that for justification to lead to knowledge, it must not be undermined by any unknown false beliefs.

Acceptance by Epistemologists

  • Support for the Condition: Many epistemologists find this analysis to be correct and sufficient to address cases like those presented by Gettier.

  • Refinement of Knowledge Definition: The addition of the no-defeaters condition refines the traditional JTB (justified true belief) account to handle cases involving luck and false assumptions.

Casual Accounts of Knowledge

  • Causal accounts of knowledge emerge as an alternative to the traditional Justified True Belief (JTB) account in response to the Gettier problem, which reveals that the JTB criteria can be met without constituting true knowledge due to the involvement of luck. 

  • Gettier-type examples demonstrate situations where a belief is justified and true but the connection between the truth and justification involves an element of luck.

Connection Between Truth and Justification:

  • Traditional JTB requires a belief to be justified and true, but Gettier examples show that this is not sufficient for knowledge because the justification and truth can be coincidentally aligned due to luck.

  • In true knowledge cases, the same factors should be responsible for both the justification and the truth of the belief. For instance, a working clock justifies the belief about the time and simultaneously ensures its truth.

Role of Causality:

  • Causal accounts propose that for a belief to be considered knowledge, there must be a direct causal link between the fact that makes the belief true and the person’s belief in that proposition.

  • This approach preserves the truth condition, as the proposition must reflect a fact for a causal relationship to exist.

Incompatibility with Fallibilism:

  • Fallibilism is the notion that a belief can be justified yet false.

    • Causal accounts, however, imply that if there is a causal connection, the belief cannot be false, thus opposing the idea of fallibilism.

  • Causal accounts do not inherently address justification.

    • However, one might attempt to reformulate fallibilism in new terms to reconcile it with causal accounts, though this would require significant modification.

Implications of Causal Accounts:

  • Gettier Problems:

    • Causal accounts aim to eliminate the luck element seen in Gettier cases by ensuring a direct causal link between the fact and the belief, thus resolving the misalignment between truth and justification.

  • Knowledge Definition:

    • Shifts from needing a separate justification condition to focusing on the causal relationship, simplifying the criteria for knowledge but also complicating its practical assessment.

Example:

  • Consider the scenario where you look at a properly functioning clock to determine the time:

  • JTB View: You believe the time is 11:56 because the clock says so (justified), and it is indeed 11:56 (true).

  • Gettier Example: If the clock stopped exactly 24 hours ago at 11:56, your belief is justified (based on the clock) and true (by coincidence) but not knowledge due to the luck element.

  • Causal Account: Your belief that the time is 11:56 is knowledge only if there is a direct causal link between the actual time (fact) and your belief (looking at the working clock), eliminating the coincidental nature.

Nature of Justification

  • The concept of justification is central to the Gettier problem and the analysis of knowledge, yet it remains elusive.

  • To better understand justification, we need to consider how it contributes to the goal of forming true beliefs while avoiding error.

  • This goal implies that justified beliefs are those formed in a way that optimally pursues truth.

  • When we evaluate whether a belief is justified, we essentially assess whether the belief matches the world and whether this match was achieved correctly.

Two Approaches to Justification:

Internalist Approach (Believer's Mind):

  • This perspective focuses on the mental states and processes of the believer.

  • Justification is about the cognitive processes, evidence, and reasons available to the believer.

  • The belief is justified if it is supported by adequate reasons or evidence from the believer's perspective.

  • Emphasizes access to and awareness of justifying factors, suggesting that a belief is justified if the believer can internally verify its truth.

Externalist Approach (The World):

  • This perspective emphasizes the relationship between the belief and the external world.

  • Justification depends on factors outside the believer’s mental states, such as the reliability of the belief-forming process.

  • A belief is justified if it is produced by a process that reliably leads to truth, regardless of the believer's awareness of this reliability.

  • Focuses on the objective connection between the belief and the actual state of affairs in the world.

Implications and Challenges:

Internalism:

  • Provides a clear criterion for the believer to assess justification.

  • Faces challenges in explaining how internal access to reasons or evidence guarantees truth.

  • May struggle with the problem of infinite regress, where justifying beliefs require further justifications.

Externalism:

  • Avoids the regress problem by grounding justification in reliable processes.

  • Can account for justified beliefs even when the believer is unaware of the reliability.

  • May be criticized for disconnecting justification from the believer's perspective and subjective experience.

The Gettier Problem and Justification:

  • Gettier cases illustrate situations where a belief is true and justified yet fails to constitute knowledge due to luck.

  • These cases highlight a gap in the traditional understanding of justification.

  • By exploring internalist and externalist approaches, we aim to refine our understanding of justification to address this gap.

Internalism

  • Core Idea: Justification of a belief is determined solely by factors internal to the believer’s mind.

  • Mental States: Beliefs, sensory inputs (sense data), and beliefs about the relations between various beliefs.

Belief Formation:

  • Mental Process: Beliefs are formed through mental processes involving other mental states.

  • Justification Criteria: For a belief to be justified, it must be supported by other justified mental states.

Basing or Support Relation:

  • Entailment vs. Probability:

    • Entailment: If belief A is based on belief B, the truth of B must entail the truth of A.

    • Probabilistic Support: To allow for fallibility, B must provide good reasons to believe that A is true, making it likely or probable.

Good Reason for Belief:

  • Essential Part of Internalism: A good reason is necessary to establish the justification of a belief.

  • Justified Supporting Beliefs: Belief B must itself be justified to confer justification on belief A.

Regress Problem:

  • Issue of Infinite Justification:

    • Chain of Justification: If belief B must be justified by another belief C, and C by D, this leads to a potential infinite regress.

  • Four Possibilities:

    • Infinite Regress: The series of justified beliefs continues infinitely.

    • Circular Justification: The series of justified beliefs circles back to its beginning (e.g., A is based on B, B on C, C on D, and D on A).

    • Unjustified Starting Point: The series of justified beliefs begins with an unjustified belief.

    • Foundational Belief: The series begins with a belief that is justified, but not by virtue of being based on another justified belief.

Implications for Internalism:

  • Deciding Among Alternatives: An internalist account must choose among these possibilities to provide a coherent theory of justification.

Foundationalism

Regress Argument Analysis:

  • Rejecting Alternatives:

    • Infinite Regress: Unacceptable because the human mind has a finite number of beliefs, and belief formation must start somewhere.

    • Circular Justification: Fallacious because it involves reasoning in a circle.

    • Unjustified Starting Point: Invalid because it makes all subsequent beliefs unjustified.

Conclusion:

  • Alternative 4 is correct by elimination: Some beliefs (basic beliefs) must be justified independently of other beliefs.

Types of Justified Beliefs:

  • Basic Beliefs:

    • Definition: Beliefs that initiate a chain of justification and do not derive their justification from other beliefs.

    • Role: Confer justification on other, non-basic beliefs.

    • Justification Source: Must be justified in a way other than by relations to other beliefs (self-justified or from a non-doxastic source).

  • Non-Basic Beliefs:

    • Definition: Beliefs that derive their justification from other beliefs.

    • Role: Dependent on basic beliefs for their justification.

Asymmetrical Relationship:

  • Structure of Justification:

    • Asymmetry: If belief A is based on belief B, B cannot be based on A.

    • Foundational Structure: Basic beliefs serve as the foundation for non-basic beliefs, creating a non-circular and non-infinite structure of justified beliefs.

Source of Justification for Basic Beliefs:

  • Self-Justified Beliefs: Beliefs that justify themselves inherently without reliance on other beliefs.

  • Non-Doxastic Sources: Sensory inputs or other external factors that provide justification without being beliefs themselves.

Coherentism

Critique of Foundationalism:

  • Dissatisfaction with Foundationalism: Internalists might reject the idea that some beliefs can be justified without being based on other beliefs.

  • Flaw in the Regress Problem: The problem assumes that justification is linear, with beliefs supporting other beliefs in a hierarchical, asymmetrical manner.

Coherentist Approach:

  • Holistic Justification:

    • Mutual Support: Beliefs derive their justification from being part of a coherent set of beliefs that support each other.

    • Non-Linear: Justification is not a linear chain but a network where each belief is justified by its relationship with the entire system of beliefs.

  • Coherence Criteria:

    • Beyond Consistency: Coherence must involve more than logical consistency; there must be a positive support relationship among beliefs.

    • Explanatory Relationship: The beliefs in a coherent set should support each other in a way that they explain or reinforce one another.

Isolation Objection:

  • Potential Problem:

    • Isolated Coherence: A set of beliefs can be coherent yet disconnected from reality.

    • For example, a fictional narrative can be internally coherent but not justified as knowledge about the real world.

Implications for Internalism:

  • Reality Connection: Justification requires not just internal coherence but also a match between beliefs and the actual world.

  • Challenge for Coherentism: To address the isolation objection, coherentists must find a way to ensure that a coherent set of beliefs is also connected to reality.

Externalism

  • Externalism: Justification depends on factors external to the believer’s mind. This approach addresses the isolation objection by ensuring that beliefs are connected to reality.

Reliabilism: The Prominent Version of Externalism

  • Belief Formation Sources:

    • Sources of Beliefs: Sense experience, reason, testimony, memory, etc.

    • Cognitive Processes: The specific processes (e.g., vision, expert testimony) that lead to the formation of beliefs.

Reliability Criterion:

  • Core Principle: A belief is justified if it results from a cognitive process that reliably produces true beliefs.

  • Examples:

    • Vision: Reliable for a normally-sighted person observing a well-lit object.

    • Testimony: Reliable when coming from an expert, unreliable when from a compulsive liar.

The Generality Problem

  • Challenge in Specification:

    • Describing Processes: Cognitive processes can be described at various levels of generality (e.g., vision by a normally-sighted person vs. vision by a normally-sighted person in daylight while looking at an elm tree).

    • Impact on Reliability: Some descriptions might specify a reliable process, while others might not, affecting the justification status of the belief.

Implication:

  • Need for Precision: To determine whether a belief is justified, one must specify the appropriate level of generality for the cognitive process.

The Truetemp Problem (Keith Lehrer)

  • Scenario:

    • Mr. Truetemp: A person with a tempucomp device implanted in his brain that accurately reads the temperature and causes spontaneous true beliefs about it.

    • Unawareness: Truetemp is unaware of the device and its function.

Lehrer's Argument:

  • Ignorance Issue: Truetemp’s ignorance about the source of his true beliefs renders those beliefs unjustified.

  • Awareness Requirement: Lehrer concludes that a belief-forming process must not only be reliable but also that the believer must be aware of the reliability of the process for the beliefs to be justified.

The Extent of Human Knowledge

Sources of Knowledge

  • Empirical Knowledge:

    • Perception and Senses: Empirical facts about the physical world are known through the senses (sight, hearing, smell, touch, taste).

    • Scientific Method: Science exemplifies empirical knowledge through data collection and experiments.

    • Everyday Perception: Most mundane knowledge about our environment is acquired through our sensory experiences.

Reasoning and Inference:

  • Data Analysis: Scientists must analyze collected data to derive knowledge.

  • Inferences: We draw inferences from sensory information to form knowledge.

  • Abstract/Non-Empirical Knowledge: Knowledge of abstract or a priori facts relies on reasoning rather than sensory experience.

Intuition:

  • Direct Access: Intuition is believed to provide direct access to a priori knowledge without needing empirical evidence.

Sustaining and Transmitting Knowledge

  • Memory:

    • Retaining Knowledge: Memory enables us to retain knowledge over time.

    • Past Justification: We can remember something known in the past even if we forget the original justification for that knowledge.

  • Testimony:

    • Knowledge Transmission: Knowledge can be passed from one person to another through testimony.

    • Trusted Sources: Belief in the truth of a proposition can be justified by the testimony of a trusted source.

Skepticism

  • Core Idea: Skepticism is the view that we do not, or cannot, have knowledge, or that we know much less than we think we do.

Types of Skepticism:

  • Local Skepticism:

    • Domain-Specific Doubts: Skepticism concerning specific areas such as mathematics, morality, or the external world.

    • Common Example: Skepticism about the external world is the most well-known form.

  • Global Skepticism:

    • Universal Doubt: The belief that we cannot know anything at all.

Focus of Skepticism:

  • Truth vs. Justification:

    • Truth Skepticism: The view that none of our beliefs are true.

    • Justification Skepticism: The view that none of our beliefs are justified (more common than truth skepticism).

Arguments for Skepticism

  • General Strategy:

    • Challenging Knowledge Claims: Skeptics often question how we know what we claim to know.

    • Need for Argument: Simply questioning knowledge isn't enough; skepticism must be supported by robust arguments.

Prominent Arguments for External World Skepticism

  • Argument from Illusion:

    • Premise: Our senses can deceive us, as evidenced by illusions and hallucinations.

    • Conclusion: If our senses are not always reliable, then we cannot trust them to provide knowledge about the external world.

  • Brain in a Vat Argument:

    • Premise: It's possible that we are brains in vats, experiencing a simulated reality created by some external source.

    • Conclusion: If we cannot rule out this possibility, then we cannot be sure that our sensory experiences correspond to an external reality.

Cartesian Skepticism

  • Skepticism: Descartes explores the possibility that all our beliefs might be unjustified due to systematic deception.

Key Points of Descartes' Argument

  • Inaccuracy of Perceptions:

    • Sensory Deception: Our senses sometimes deceive us (e.g., optical illusions).

    • Dreams vs. Reality: We occasionally mistake dreams for waking experiences, making it difficult to distinguish between them.

  • Evil Demon Hypothesis:

    • Possibility of Deception: It's conceivable that an evil demon is deceiving us, making all our experiences false.

    • Modern Version: The "brain-in-a-vat" scenario, where a brain connected to a computer in a vat receives simulated experiences, illustrates this deception.

Implications of the Argument

  • Unjustified Beliefs:

    • False Beliefs: If some perceptions are false, then some of our beliefs based on these perceptions are also false.

    • Need for Distinction: To be justified in our beliefs, we need a reliable method to distinguish between true and false beliefs.

  • Indistinguishability Problem:

    • Waking vs. Dreaming: No definitive signs distinguish waking life from dreams.

    • Trustworthy vs. Untrustworthy Beliefs: Similarly, no signs distinguish accurate beliefs from those caused by an evil demon or brain-in-a-vat scenario.

Conclusion of the Argument

  • All Beliefs Unjustified: Since we cannot reliably distinguish between true and false beliefs, all our beliefs are potentially unjustified.

  • Skepticism: This leads to a skeptical conclusion that we cannot know anything with certainty.

Descartes' Response to Skepticism in Later Meditations

  • Method of Doubt:

    • Descartes uses hyperbolic doubt to question all beliefs, aiming to find something indubitable.

  • Cogito Ergo Sum ("I think, therefore I am"):

    • Indubitable Belief: Descartes finds that while he can doubt everything, he cannot doubt that he is thinking and therefore exists as a thinking being.

    • Foundation for Knowledge: This becomes the foundational belief upon which he rebuilds his system of knowledge.

  • Existence of God:

    • Proof of a Benevolent God: Descartes argues for the existence of a benevolent God who would not deceive him.

    • Reliability of Clear and Distinct Perceptions: If a benevolent God exists, then clear and distinct perceptions can be trusted as true.

  • Distinguishing Truth from Falsehood:

    • Clear and Distinct Criterion: Descartes proposes that beliefs derived from clear and distinct perceptions are true.

    • Overcoming Skepticism: This provides a way to distinguish between true and false beliefs, countering the skeptical argument.

Humean Skepticism

  • Core Idea:

    • Limitations of Perception: Our senses only provide information about how things appear at a given moment, not about how things actually are or about the unobserved parts of the universe.

    • Role of Reason: Reason is needed to extend our knowledge beyond immediate sensory experiences.

Hume's Critique of Reason

  • Problem of Induction:

    • Inductive Reasoning: We often use past experiences to make generalizations about the future (e.g., the sun has risen every day, so it will rise tomorrow).

    • Hume's Critique: Hume argues that inductive reasoning lacks rational justification.

      • Just because something has happened in the past does not guarantee it will happen in the future.

      • There is no logical necessity connecting past and future events.

  • Causal Inference:

    • Causation: We believe that one event causes another based on our experiences (e.g., striking a match causes it to light).

    • Hume's Critique: Hume contends that our belief in causation is not grounded in reason but in habit or custom.

      • We observe sequences of events and infer a causal connection, but this inference is not rationally justified.

      • We never perceive causation directly; we only see one event following another.

Key Points of Hume's Argument

  • Perception Limits:

    • Immediate Sensory Data: Our senses only provide immediate and limited information about our current environment.

    • Beyond Immediate Perception: Knowledge about anything beyond what we currently perceive cannot be solely derived from the senses.

  • Role of Habit and Custom:

    • Inductive Habit: Our expectation that the future will resemble the past is based on habit, not rational justification.

    • Customary Beliefs: Our beliefs about causation and the unobserved world are customary, formed through repeated associations rather than through reason.

  • Skeptical Conclusion:

    • Unjustified Beliefs: Since reason cannot justify inductive reasoning or causal inferences, our beliefs about the external world beyond immediate perception are unjustified.

    • Persistent Skepticism: Even if we trust our senses, we face skepticism regarding any knowledge claims extending beyond our immediate sensory experiences.

Language and Meaning

  • Language is essential for expressing and communicating knowledge.

  • Philosophical inquiry into language explores how meaning is constructed and understood.

  • Meaning: The significance or interpretation of words and sentences. Theories of meaning include:

    • Referential Theory: Words refer to objects or concepts in the world.

    • Use Theory: Meaning is derived from how words are used in practice (Ludwig Wittgenstein).

    • Truth-Conditional Semantics: The meaning of a sentence is given by the conditions under which it is true.

Truth, Coherence, Correspondence, and Pragmatism

  • These theories offer different criteria for evaluating the truth of statements:

  • Correspondence Theory: A statement is true if it corresponds to a fact or reality.

  • Coherence Theory: A statement is true if it coheres with a consistent system of interconnected beliefs.

  • Pragmatic Theory: A statement is true if it is useful and works in practical terms.

Grammarian Philosophies: A Classical Indian Approach

  • Classical Indian epistemology provides rich insights into the nature of knowledge and the role of language:

  • Nyaya School: Emphasizes logical analysis, debate, and the four means of acquiring knowledge: perception, inference, comparison, and testimony.

  • Buddhist Epistemology: Focuses on perception and inference, with a critical examination of the self and the nature of reality. Key figures include Dignaga and Dharmakirti.

  • Mimamsa and Vedanta: Explore the role of Vedic texts and direct experience in understanding reality. Mimamsa emphasizes ritual and dharma, while Vedanta focuses on metaphysical questions about Brahman and the self.

Challenges to Knowledge and Confirmation of Knowledge

Realism and Skepticism

  • Realism: The view that an external reality exists independently of our perceptions. Realists argue that we can know the world through our sensory experiences and rational inferences.

  • Skepticism: Doubts the possibility of certain knowledge. Skeptics argue that our senses and reasoning are fallible, and thus, we can never achieve absolute certainty.

Arguments from Illusion and Mysticism

  • Illusion: Perceptual errors that challenge the reliability of sensory knowledge. For example, a stick appears bent when partially submerged in water.

  • Mysticism: Claims knowledge through direct, often ineffable, spiritual or transcendental experiences. Mystical knowledge is seen as beyond ordinary sensory or rational understanding.

Subjectivism and Objectivism

  • Subjectivism: The view that knowledge is influenced by individual perspectives and experiences. Truth and justification are seen as relative to the subject.

  • Objectivism: The view that knowledge and truth exist independently of individual beliefs or perceptions. There are objective standards for justification and truth.

Causal Theory, Idealism, Phenomenalism, Perspectivism

Causal Theory

  • The causal theory of knowledge suggests that beliefs are justified when they are caused by the relevant facts or states of affairs in the right way.

  • For instance, seeing a tree and believing that there is a tree because you see it.

Idealism

  • Idealism posits that reality is fundamentally mental or immaterial.

  • Major proponents like George Berkeley argue that objects only exist as perceptions in our minds, and there is no material substance underlying them.

Phenomenalism

  • Phenomenalism claims that physical objects do not exist independently of our sensory experiences.

  • Instead, objects are logical constructions from sensory experiences.

  • This view is closely associated with philosophers like John Stuart Mill.

Perspectivism

  • Perspectivism, associated with Friedrich Nietzsche, suggests that all knowledge is from a particular perspective and that there are no objective truths.

  • Knowledge and truth are seen as contingent on individual or cultural perspectives.

Theories of Justification

  • Justification is the process or reasons that support our beliefs and distinguish knowledge from mere belief.

  • Various theories include:

  • Foundationalism: Beliefs are justified based on basic, self-evident truths or foundational beliefs that do not require further justification.

  • Coherentism: Beliefs are justified by their coherence with other beliefs in a mutually supportive system. There are no foundational beliefs, but rather a web of interconnected beliefs.

  • Reliabilism: Beliefs are justified if they are produced by reliable cognitive processes or methods that generally lead to true beliefs.

  • Virtue Epistemology: Justification depends on the intellectual virtues of the knower, such as open-mindedness, intellectual courage, and intellectual humility.

Knowledge Around the World

Access to Knowledge

  • Access to knowledge varies widely across the globe, influenced by factors such as socioeconomic status, education systems, cultural norms, and political regimes.

  • The digital divide highlights disparities in access to information and technology.

Knowledge and Technology

  • Technology profoundly impacts how knowledge is created, shared, and accessed.

  • The internet, digital media, and artificial intelligence are transforming the landscape of knowledge, raising issues of information overload, digital literacy, and the ethics of technology use.

Knowledge and Power

  • Knowledge is closely linked to power structures. The control and dissemination of knowledge can reinforce or challenge social inequalities.

  • The concept of "knowledge is power" underscores how those who control knowledge can influence societal norms, policies, and governance.